Playfair's axiom

In geometry, Playfair's axiom is an axiom that can be used instead of the fifth postulate of Euclid (the parallel postulate):

In a plane, given a line and a point not on it, at most one line parallel to the given line can be drawn through the point.[1]

Antecedent of Playfair's axiom: a line and a point not on the line
Consequent of Playfair's axiom: a second line, parallel to the first, passing through the point

It is equivalent to Euclid's parallel postulate in the context of Euclidean geometry[2] and was named after the Scottish mathematician John Playfair. The "at most" clause is all that is needed since it can be proved from the first four axioms that at least one parallel line exists given a line L and a point P not on L, as follows:

  1. Construct a perpendicular: Using the axioms and previously established theorems, you can construct a line perpendicular to line L that passes through P.
  2. Construct another perpendicular: A second perpendicular line is drawn to the first one, starting from point P.
  3. Parallel Line: This second perpendicular line will be parallel to L by the definition of parallel lines (i.e the alternate interior angles are congruent as per the 4th axiom).

The statement is often written with the phrase, "there is one and only one parallel". In Euclid's Elements, two lines are said to be parallel if they never meet and other characterizations of parallel lines are not used.[3][4]

This axiom is used not only in Euclidean geometry but also in the broader study of affine geometry where the concept of parallelism is central. In the affine geometry setting, the stronger form of Playfair's axiom (where "at most one" is replaced by "one and only one") is needed since the axioms of neutral geometry are not present to provide a proof of existence. Playfair's version of the axiom has become so popular that it is often referred to as Euclid's parallel axiom,[5] even though it was not Euclid's version of the axiom.

History

Proclus (410485 A.D.) clearly makes the statement in his commentary on Euclid I.31 (Book I, Proposition 31).[6]

In 1785 William Ludlam expressed the parallel axiom as follows:[7]

Two straight lines, meeting at a point, are not both parallel to a third line.

This brief expression of Euclidean parallelism was adopted by Playfair in his textbook Elements of Geometry (1795) that was republished often. He wrote[8]

Two straight lines which intersect one another cannot be both parallel to the same straight line.

Playfair acknowledged Ludlam and others for simplifying the Euclidean assertion. In later developments the point of intersection of the two lines came first, and the denial of two parallels became expressed as a unique parallel through the given point.[9]

In 1883 Arthur Cayley was president of the British Association and expressed this opinion in his address to the Association:[10]

My own view is that Euclid's Twelfth Axiom in Playfair's form of it, does not need demonstration, but is part of our notion of space, of the physical space of our experience, which is the representation lying at the bottom of all external experience.

When David Hilbert wrote his book, Foundations of Geometry (1899),[11] providing a new set of axioms for Euclidean geometry, he used Playfair's form of the axiom instead of the original Euclidean version for discussing parallel lines.[12]

Relation with Euclid's fifth postulate

If the sum of the interior angles α and β is less than 180°, the two straight lines, produced indefinitely, meet on that side.

Euclid's parallel postulate states:

If a line segment intersects two straight lines forming two interior angles on the same side that sum to less than two right angles, then the two lines, if extended indefinitely, meet on that side on which the angles sum to less than two right angles.[13]

The complexity of this statement when compared to Playfair's formulation is certainly a leading contribution to the popularity of quoting Playfair's axiom in discussions of the parallel postulate.

Within the context of absolute geometry the two statements are equivalent, meaning that each can be proved by assuming the other in the presence of the remaining axioms of the geometry. This is not to say that the statements are logically equivalent (i.e., one can be proved from the other using only formal manipulations of logic), since, for example, when interpreted in the spherical model of elliptical geometry one statement is true and the other isn't.[14] Logically equivalent statements have the same truth value in all models in which they have interpretations.

The proofs below assume that all the axioms of absolute (neutral) geometry are valid.

Euclid's fifth postulate implies Playfair's axiom

The easiest way to show this is using the Euclidean theorem (equivalent to the fifth postulate) that states that the angles of a triangle sum to two right angles. Given a line and a point P not on that line, construct a line, t, perpendicular to the given one through the point P, and then a perpendicular to this perpendicular at the point P. This line is parallel because it cannot meet and form a triangle, which is stated in Book 1 Proposition 27 in Euclid's Elements.[15] Now it can be seen that no other parallels exist. If n was a second line through P, then n makes an acute angle with t (since it is not the perpendicular) and the hypothesis of the fifth postulate holds, and so, n meets .[16]

Playfair's axiom implies Euclid's fifth postulate

Given that Playfair's postulate implies that only the perpendicular to the perpendicular is a parallel, the lines of the Euclid construction will have to cut each other in a point. It is also necessary to prove that they will do it in the side where the angles sum to less than two right angles, but this is more difficult.[17]

Importance of triangle congruence

The classical equivalence between Playfair's axiom and Euclid's fifth postulate collapses in the absence of triangle congruence.[18] This is shown by constructing a geometry that redefines angles in a way that respects Hilbert's axioms of incidence, order, and congruence, except for the Side-Angle-Side (SAS) congruence. This geometry models the classical Playfair's axiom but not Euclid's fifth postulate.

Transitivity of parallelism

Proposition 30 of Euclid reads, "Two lines, each parallel to a third line, are parallel to each other." It was noted[19] by Augustus De Morgan that this proposition is logically equivalent to Playfair’s axiom. This notice was recounted[20] by T. L. Heath in 1908. De Morgan’s argument runs as follows: Let X be the set of pairs of distinct lines which meet and Y the set of distinct pairs of lines each of which is parallel to a single common line. If z represents a pair of distinct lines, then the statement,

For all z, if z is in X then z is not in Y,

is Playfair's axiom (in De Morgan's terms, No X is Y) and its logically equivalent contrapositive,

For all z, if z is in Y then z is not in X,

is Euclid I.30, the transitivity of parallelism (No Y is X).

More recently the implication has been phrased differently in terms of the binary relation expressed by parallel lines: In affine geometry the relation is taken to be an equivalence relation, which means that a line is considered to be parallel to itself. Andy Liu[21] wrote, "Let P be a point not on line 2. Suppose both line 1 and line 3 pass through P and are parallel to line 2. By transitivity, they are parallel to each other, and hence cannot have exactly P in common. It follows that they are the same line, which is Playfair's axiom."

Notes

  1. Playfair 1846, p. 29
  2. more precisely, in the context of absolute geometry.
  3. Euclid's elements, Book I, definition 23
  4. Heath 1956, Vol. 1, p. 190
  5. for instance, Rafael Artzy (1965) Linear Geometry, page 202, Addison-Wesley
  6. Heath 1956, Vol. 1, p. 220
  7. William Ludlam (1785) The Rudiments of Mathematics, p. 145, Cambridge
  8. Playfair 1846, p. 11
  9. Playfair 1846, p. 291
  10. William Barrett Frankland (1910) Theories of Parallelism: A Historic Critique, page 31, Cambridge University Press
  11. Hilbert, David (1990) [1971], Foundations of Geometry [Grundlagen der Geometrie], translated by Leo Unger from the 10th German edition (2nd English ed.), La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing, ISBN 0-87548-164-7
  12. Eves 1963, pp. 385-7
  13. George Phillips (1826) Elements of Geometry (containing the first six books of Euclid), p. 3, Baldwin, Cradock, and Joy
  14. Henderson, David W.; Taimiņa, Daina (2005), Experiencing Geometry: Euclidean and Non-Euclidean with History (3rd ed.), Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall, p. 139, ISBN 0-13-143748-8
  15. This argument assumes more than is needed to prove the result. There are proofs of the existence of parallels which do not assume an equivalent of the fifth postulate.
  16. Greenberg 1974, p. 107
  17. The proof may be found in Heath 1956, Vol. 1, p. 313
  18. Brown, Elizabeth T.; Castner, Emily; Davis, Stephen; O’Shea, Edwin; Seryozhenkov, Edouard; Vargas, A. J. (2019-08-01). "On the equivalence of Playfair's axiom to the parallel postulate". Journal of Geometry. 110 (2): 42. doi:10.1007/s00022-019-0496-9. ISSN 1420-8997.
  19. Supplementary Remarks on the first six Books of Euclid's Elements in the Companion to the Almanac, 1849.
  20. Heath 1956, Vol. 1, p. 314
  21. The College Mathematics Journal 42(5):372

References

(3 vols.): ISBN 0-486-60088-2 (vol. 1), ISBN 0-486-60089-0 (vol. 2), ISBN 0-486-60090-4 (vol. 3).
This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.