Semi-deterministic Büchi automaton
In automata theory, a semi-deterministic Büchi automaton (also known as Büchi automaton deterministic in the limit,[1] or limit-deterministic Büchi automaton[2]) is a special type of Büchi automaton. In such an automaton, the set of states can be partitioned into two subsets: one subset forms a deterministic automaton and also contains all the accepting states.
For every Büchi automaton, a semi-deterministic Büchi automaton can be constructed such that both recognize the same ω-language. But, a deterministic Büchi automaton may not exist for the same ω-language.
Motivation
In standard model checking against linear temporal logic (LTL) properties, it is sufficient to translate an LTL formula into a non-deterministic Büchi automaton. But, in probabilistic model checking, LTL formulae are typically translated into deterministic Rabin automata (DRA), as for instance in the PRISM tool. However, a fully deterministic automaton is not needed. Indeed, semi-deterministic Büchi automata are sufficient in probabilistic model checking.
Formal definition
A Büchi automaton (Q,Σ,∆,Q0,F) is called semi-deterministic if Q is the union of two disjoint subsets N and D such that F ⊆ D and, for every d ∈ D, automaton (D,Σ,∆,{d},F) is deterministic.
Transformation from a Büchi automaton
Any given Büchi automaton can be transformed into a semi-deterministic Büchi automaton that recognizes the same language, using following construction.
Suppose A=(Q,Σ,∆,Q0,F) is a Büchi automaton. Let Pr be a projection function which takes a set of states S and a symbol a ∈ Σ and returns set of states {q' | ∃q ∈ S and (q,a,q') ∈ ∆ }. The equivalent semi-deterministic Büchi automaton is A'=(N ∪ D,Σ,∆',Q'0,F'), where
- N = 2Q and D = 2Q×2Q
- Q'0 = {Q0}
- ∆' = ∆1 ∪ ∆2 ∪ ∆3 ∪ ∆4
- ∆1 = {( S, a, S' ) | S'=Pr(S,a) }
- ∆2 = {( S, a, ({q'},∅) ) | ∃q ∈ S and (q,a,q') ∈ ∆ }
- ∆3 = {( (L,R), a, (L',R') ) | L≠R and L'=Pr(L,a) and R'=(L'∩F)∪Pr(R,a) }
- ∆4 = {( (L,L), a, (L',R') ) | L'=Pr(L,a) and R'=(L'∩F) }
- F' = {(L,L) | L≠∅ }
Note the structure of states and transitions of A′. States of A′ are partitioned into N and D. An N-state is defined as an element of the power set of states of A. A D-state is defined as a pair of elements of power set of states of A. The transition relation of A' is the union of four parts: ∆1, ∆2, ∆3, and ∆4. The ∆1-transitions only take A' from a N-state to a N-state. Only the ∆2-transitions can take A' from an N-state to a D-state. Note that only the ∆2-transitions can cause non-determinism in A' . The ∆3 and ∆4-transitions take A' from a D-state to a D-state. By construction, A' is a semi-deterministic Büchi automaton. The proof of L(A')=L(A) follows.
For an ω-word w=a1,a2,... , let w(i,j) be the finite segment ai+1,...,aj-1,aj of w.
L(A') ⊆ L(A)
Proof: Let w ∈ L(A'). The initial state of A' is an N-state and all the accepting states in F' are D-states. Therefore, any accepting run of A' must follow ∆1 for finitely many transitions at start, then take a transition in ∆2 to move into D-states, and then take ∆3 and ∆4 transitions for ever. Let ρ' = S0,...,Sn-1,(L0,R0),(L1,R1),... be such accepting run of A' on w.
By definition of ∆2, L0 must be a singleton set. Let L0 = {s}. Due to definitions of ∆1 and ∆2, there exist a run prefix s0,...,sn-1,s of A on word w(0,n) such that sj ∈ Sj. Since ρ' is an accepting run of A' , some states in F' are visited infinitely often. Therefore, there exist a strictly increasing and infinite sequence of indexes i0,i1,... such that i0=0 and, for each j > 0, Lij=Rij and Lij≠∅. For all j > 0, let m = ij-ij-1. Due to definitions of ∆3 and ∆4, for every qm ∈ Lij, there exist a state q0 ∈ Lij-1 and a run segment q0,...,qm of A on the word segment w(n+ij-1,n+ij) such that, for some 0 < k ≤ m, qk ∈ F. We can organize the run segments collected so for via following definitions.
- Let predecessor(qm,j) = q0.
- Let run(s,0)= s0,...,sn-1,s and, for j > 0, run(qm,j)= q1,...,qm
Now the above run segments will be put together to make an infinite accepting run of A. Consider a tree whose set of nodes is ∪j≥0 Lij × {j}. The root is (s,0) and parent of a node (q,j) is (predecessor(q,j), j-1). This tree is infinite, finitely branching, and fully connected. Therefore, by Kőnig's lemma, there exists an infinite path (q0,0),(q1,1),(q2,2),... in the tree. Therefore, following is an accepting run of A
- run(q0,0)⋅run(q1,1)⋅run(q2,2)⋅...
Hence, by infinite pigeonhole principle, w is accepted by A.
L(A) ⊆ L(A')
Proof: The definition of projection function Pr can be extended such that in the second argument it can accept a finite word. For some set of states S, finite word w, and symbol a, let Pr(S,aw) = Pr(Pr(S,a),w) and Pr(S,ε) = S. Let w ∈ L(A) and ρ=q0,q1,... be an accepting run of A on w. First, we will prove following useful lemma.
- Lemma 1
- There is an index n such that qn ∈ F and, for all m ≥ n there exist a k > m, such that Pr({ qn },w(n,k)) = Pr({ qm },w(m,k)).
- Proof: Pr({ qn },w(n,k)) ⊇ Pr({ qm },w(m,k)) holds because there is a path from qn to qm. We will prove the converse by contradiction. Lets assume for all n, there is a m ≥ n such that for all k > m, Pr({ qn },w(n,k)) ⊃ Pr({ qm },w(m,k)) holds. Lets suppose p is the number of states in A. Therefore, there is a strictly increasing sequence of indexes n0,n1,... ,np such that, for all k > np, Pr({ qni },w(ni,k)) ⊃ Pr({ qni+1 },w(ni+1,k)). Therefore,Pr({ qnp },w(np,k)) = ∅. Contradiction.
In any run, A' can only once make a non-deterministic choice that is when it chooses to take a Δ2 transition and rest of the execution of A' is deterministic. Let n be such that it satisfies lemma 1. We make A' to take Δ2 transition at nth step. So, we define a run ρ'=S0,...,Sn-1,({qn},∅),(L1,R1),(L2,R2),... of A' on word w. We will show that ρ' is an accepting run. Li ≠ ∅ because there is an infinite run of A passing through qn. So, we are only left to show that Li=Ri occurs infinitely often. Suppose contrary then there exists an index m such that, for all i ≥ m, Li≠Ri. Let j > m such that qj+n ∈ F therefore qj+n ∈ Rj. By lemma 1, there exist k > j such that Lk = Pr({ qn },w(n,k+n)) = Pr({ qj+n },w(j+n,k+n)) ⊆ Rk. So, Lk=Rk. A contradiction has been derived. Hence, ρ' is an accepting run and w ∈ L(A').
References
- Courcoubetis, Costas; Yannakakis, Mihalis (July 1995). "The Complexity of Probabilistic Verification". J. ACM. 42 (4): 857–907. doi:10.1145/210332.210339. ISSN 0004-5411. S2CID 17872656.
- Sickert, Salomon; Esparza, Javier; Jaax, Stefan; Křetínský, Jan (2016). Chaudhuri, Swarat; Farzan, Azadeh (eds.). "Limit-Deterministic Büchi Automata for Linear Temporal Logic". Computer Aided Verification. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer International Publishing. 9780: 312–332. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-41540-6_17. ISBN 978-3-319-41540-6.