Heraclitus

Heraclitus of Ephesus (/ˌhɛrəˈkltəs/; Greek: Ἡράκλειτος Herákleitos, "Glory of Hera"; fl.c.500 BCE)[1] was an ancient Greek pre-Socratic philosopher from the city of Ephesus, which was then part of the Persian Empire.

Heraclitus
Bronze bust of Heraclitus of Ephesus, National Archaeological Museum, Naples, Italy
Bornc.6th century BCE
Ephesus, Ionia, Persian Empire (now Selçuk, İzmir, Turkey)
Diedc.5th century BCE
EraAncient
RegionAncient Greece
SchoolPre-Socratic
Main interests
Nature, Soul, Cosmology, Fire
Notable ideas
Unity of opposites, Flux
Influences
Influenced

Little is known of Heraclitus's life. He wrote a single work, only fragments of which have survived. Most of the ancient stories about him are later fabrications based on interpretations of the preserved fragments. His paradoxical philosophy and appreciation for wordplay and cryptic utterances has earned him the epithet "the obscure" since antiquity. He was considered a misanthrope who was subject to melancholia. Consequently, he became known as "the weeping philosopher" in contrast to the ancient philosopher Democritus, who was known as "the laughing philosopher".

The central idea of Heraclitus' philosophy is the unity of opposites. One of his most notable applications of this idea was to the concept of impermanence; he saw the world as constantly in flux, changing as it remained the same, which he expressed in the saying, "No man ever steps in the same river twice." This changing aspect of his philosophy is contrasted with that of the ancient philosopher Parmenides, who believed in "being" and in the static nature of the universe.

Life

Ephesus on the coast of Asia Minor, birthplace of Heraclitus

The main primary source for the life of Heraclitus is the doxographer Diogenes Laërtius; Although most of the information provided by Laertius is unreliable, the anecdote[lower-alpha 1] that Heraclitus relinquished the hereditary title of "king" to his younger brother may at least imply that Heraclitus was the eldest brother of an aristocratic family in Ephesus.[2] In the 6th century BCE, Ephesus, like other cities in Ionia, was tied to both the rise of Lydia under Croesus and to the overthrow of Croesus by Cyrus the Great.[2] Ephesus appears to have cultivated a close relationship with the Achaemenid Empire; during the suppression of the Ionian revolt in 494 BCE, Ephesus was spared and emerged as the dominant Greek city in Ionia.[2] As the eldest son of one of the richest families in the city, Heraclitus appears to have had little sympathy for democracy,[2] but he was "an unconditional partisan of the rich."[2] but instead as "withdrawn from competing factions"[2] - similar to Solon of Athens.[2]

Heraclitus is traditionally considered to have flourished in the 69th Olympiad (504-501 BCE),[3][lower-alpha 2] but this date may simply be based on a prior account synchronizing his life with the reign of Darius the Great.[2] Two extant letters between Heraclitus and Darius I, which are quoted by Diogenes Laërtius, are also later forgeries.[4] However, this date can be considered "roughly accurate" based on a fragment[lower-alpha 3] that references Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Hecataeus as older contemporaries, which would place him near the end of the sixth century BCE.[2]

Writings

A modern reconstruction of the Temple of Artemis, located in Istanbul. According to Diogenes Laertius, Heraclitus deposited his book in the original Temple of Artemis in Ephesus.

Heraclitus is said to have produced a single work on papyrus,[lower-alpha 4] which has not survived; however, over 100 fragments of this work survive in quotations by other authors. The title is unknown,[5] but many later philosophers in this period refer to this work as On Nature.[lower-alpha 5] Diogenes Laertius states that the book was divided into three parts,[lower-alpha 6] but Burnet notes that "it is not to be supposed that this division is due to [Heraclitus] himself; all we can infer is that the work fell naturally into these parts when the Stoic commentators took their editions of it in hand.[6] Martin Litchfield West notes that the existing fragments do not give much of an idea of the overall structure,[7] but that the beginning of the discourse can probably be determined[note 1], starting with the opening lines, which are quoted by Sextus Empiricus[lower-alpha 7] Some classicists and professors of ancient philosophy have disputed which of these fragments can truly be attributed to Heraclitus.[8][9] M. M. McCabe has argued that the three statements on rivers should all be read as fragments from a discourse. McCabe suggests reading them as though they arose in succession. The three fragments "could be retained, and arranged in an argumentative sequence".[8] In McCabe's reading of the fragments, Heraclitus can be read as a philosopher capable of sustained argument, rather than just aphorism.[8]

According to Diogenes Laërtius, Heraclitus deposited the book in the Artemisium as a dedication. Kahn states:[10] "Down to the time of Plutarch and Clement, if not later, the little book of Heraclitus was available in its original form to any reader who chose to seek it out".[11] Laërtius comments on the notability of the text, stating: "The book acquired such fame that it produced partisans of his philosophy who were called Heracliteans". Prominent philosophers identified today as Heracliteans include Cratylus and Antisthenes—not to be confused with the cynic [lower-alpha 8] Aristotle quotes part of the opening line in the Rhetoric to outline the difficulty in punctuating Heraclitus without ambiguity; he debated whether "forever" applied to "being" or to "prove".[1][lower-alpha 9] Theophrastus says (in Diogenes Laërtius) "some parts of his work [are] half-finished, while other parts [made] a strange medley".[lower-alpha 10] According to Diogenes Laërtius, Timon of Phlius called Heraclitus "the Riddler" (αἰνικτής; ainiktēs), saying Heraclitus wrote his book "rather unclearly" (asaphesteron); according to Timon, this was intended to allow only the "capable" to attempt it.[lower-alpha 11] By the time of Cicero, this epithet became "The Obscure" (ὁ Σκοτεινός; ho Skoteinós) as he had spoken nimis obscurē ("too obscurely") concerning nature and had done so deliberately in order to be misunderstood.[lower-alpha 12] By the time of Simplicius of Cilicia, a 6th century neoplatonic philosopher, who mentions Heraclitus 32 times but never quotes from him, Heraclitus' work was so rare that it was unavailable even to Simplicius and the other scholars at the Platonic Academy in Athens.[12]

Flux and unity of opposites

Relief of Dike in Ephesus. Accoding to Aristotle, Heraclitus considered strife a fundamental part of a just world.

The hallmark of Heraclitus' philosophy is flux and the unity of opposites: Diogenes Laërtius summarizes Heraclitus's philosophy, stating; "All things come into being by conflict of opposites, and the sum of things (τὰ ὅλα ta hola ("the whole")) flows like a stream".[lower-alpha 13] Two fragments relating to this concept state, "As the same thing in us is living and dead, waking and sleeping, young and old. For these things having changed around are those, and those in turn having changed around are these" (B88) and "Cold things warm up, the hot cools off, wet becomes dry, dry becomes wet" (B126).[13]

Heraclitus' doctrine on the unity of opposites suggests that unity of the world and its various parts is kept through the tension produced by the opposites. Furthermore, each polar substance contains its opposite, in a continual circular exchange and motion that results in the stability of the cosmos.[14] Another of Heraclitus' famous axioms highlights this doctrine (B53): "War is father of all and king of all; and some he manifested as gods, some as men; some he made slaves, some free", where war means the creative tension that brings things into existence.[15] In this union of opposites, of both generation and destruction, Heraclitus called the oppositional processes ἔρις (eris), "strife", and hypothesizes the apparently stable state, δίκη (dikê), "justice", is a harmony of it, which Anaximander described as injustice.[16] Aristotle said Heraclitus disliked Homer because Homer wished that strife would leave the world, which according to Heraclitus would destroy the world; "there would be no harmony without high and low notes, and no animals without male and female, which are opposites".[lower-alpha 14]

Jonathan Barnes states that "Panta rhei, 'everything flows' is probably the most familiar of Heraclitus' sayings, yet few modern scholars think he said it."[17] Barnes observes that although the exact phrase is not ascribed to Heraclitus until the 6th century by Simplicius of Cilicia, a similar saying representing the same theory,[17] panta chorei, or "everything moves" is ascribed to Heraclitus by Plato in the Cratylus.[lower-alpha 15]

Since Plato, Heraclitus's theory of Flux has been associated with the metaphor of a flowing river, that which cannot be stepped into twice.[1] This fragment from Heraclitus's writings has survived in three different forms:[17][lower-alpha 16] The German classicist and philosopher Karl-Martin Dietz interprets the metaphor as illustrating what is stable, rather than the usual interpretation of illustrating change. "You will not find anything, in which the river remains constant ... Just the fact, that there is a particular river bed, that there is a source and an estuary etc. is something, that stays identical. And this is ... the concept of a river."[18] There, Heraclitus claims we can not step into the same river twice, a position summarized with the slogan ta panta rhei (everything flows). One fragment[lower-alpha 17] reads: "Into the same rivers we both step and do not step; we both are and are not" ). Heraclitus is seemingly suggesting that not only the river is constantly changing, but we do as well, even hinting at existential questions about humankind.[19]

Cosmology

An Eternal flame from a Zoroastrian fire temple in Yazd, Iran. The role of fire in the philosophy of Heraclitus has been compared with the practice of fire worship in Zoroastrianism, which was the state religion of the Achaemenid Empire during Heraclitus' life.

Like the Milesians before him, Thales with water, Anaximander with apeiron, and Anaximenes with air, Heraclitus was considered by Aristotle to have fire as the Arche, the fundamental element that gave rise to the other elements.[20] In one fragment[lower-alpha 18], Heraclitus writes: This world-order [Kosmos], the same of all, no god nor man did create, but it ever was and is and will be: everliving fire, kindling in measures and being quenched in measures. From fire all things originate and all things return to it again in a process of eternal cycles. Heraclitus regarded the soul as a mixture of fire and water, and that fire is the noble part of the soul and water is the ignoble part, and he considered mastery of one's worldly desires to be a noble pursuit that purified the soul's fire.[21] These everlasting modifications explain his view that the cosmos was and is and will be.[22]

Heraclitus' description of a doctrine of purification of fire has also been investigated for influence from the Zoroastrian concept of Atar.[23] Many of the doctrines of Zoroastrian fire do not match exactly with those of Heraclitus, such as the relation of fire to earth, but he may have taken some inspiration from them.[23] Zoroastrian parallels to Heraclitus are often difficult to identify specifically due to a lack of surviving Zoroastrian literature from the period and mutual influence with Greek philosophy; the 9th century CE Dadestan-i_Denig preserves information on Zoroastrian cosmology, but also shows direct borrowings from Aristotle.[24] The interchange of other elements with fire also has parallels in Vedic literature from the same time period, such as the Kaushitaki Upanishad and Taittiriya Upanishad.[24] and West stresses that these doctrines of the interchange of elements were common throughout written work on philosophy that has survived from that period, so Heraclitus' doctrine of fire can not be definitively be said to have been influenced by any other particular Iranian or Indian influence, but may have been part of a mutual interchange of influence over time across the Ancient Near East.[25]

The phrase Ethos anthropoi daimon ("man's character is [his] fate") attributed to Heraclitus has led to numerous interpretations, and might mean one's luck is related to one's character.[1] The translation of daimon in this context to mean "fate" is disputed; according to Thomas Cooksey, it lends much sense to Heraclitus's observations and conclusions about human nature in general. While the translation as "fate" is generally accepted as in Charles Kahn's "a man's character is his divinity."

A fundamental term in Heraclitus is logos, an ancient Greek word with a variety of meanings; Heraclitus might have used a different meaning of the word with each usage in his book. Logos seems like a universal law that unites the cosmos, according to a fragment: "Listening not to me but to the logos, it is wise to agree (homologein) that all things are one."[lower-alpha 19] While logos is everywhere, very few people are familiar with it. Another fragment[lower-alpha 20] reads: [hoi polloi] "...do not know how to listen [to Logos] or how to speak [the truth]"[26] Heraclitus' thought on logos influenced the Stoics, who referred to him to support their belief that rational law governs the universe.[27]

Although many of the later Stoics interpreted Heraclitus as having a "logos-doctrine" where the "logos[lower-alpha 21]" was a first principle that ran through all things, West[28] observes that Plato, Aristotle, Theophrastus, and Sextus Empiricus all make no mention of this doctrine, and concludes that the language and thought are "obviously Stoic" and not attributable to Heraclitus.[28] Kahn stresses that Heraclitus used the word in multiple senses[10] and Guthrie observes that there is no evidence Heraclitus used it in a way that was significantly different from that in which it was used by contemporaneous speakers of Greek.[29] Guthrie considers the Logos as a public fact like a proposition or formula, though he admits that Heraclitus would not have considered these facts as abstract objects or immaterial things.[16]

Although the early Christian philosophers, following the Stoics, interpreted the logos in terms of a personal God, modern scholars do not believe these associations are represented in the original thought of Heraclitus. [30] When Heraclitus speaks of "God" he does not mean a single deity as an omnipotent and omniscient or God as Creator, the universe being eternal; he meant the divine as opposed to human, the immortal as opposed to the mortal and the cyclical as opposed to the transient; to him, it is arguably more accurate to speak of "the Divine" and not of "God".[30]

Legacy

Heraclitus painted as the weeping philosopher by Johannes Moreelse c.1630

Heraclitus' writings have exerted a wide influence on Western philosophy, including the works of Plato and Aristotle. Parmenides is generally agreed to either have influenced or have been influenced by him,[31] either as an influence or response to Heraclitean doctrines,[32] or as an extension of them.[33] Some of the writings in Hippocratic corpus also shows signs of Heraclitean themes,[lower-alpha 22][lower-alpha 23] as do some of the surviving fragments of other pre-Socratic philosophers including Empedocles and Democritus.[31] The sophists such as Protagoras may also have been influenced by Heraclitus.[34] Many of the later Stoic, Cynic, and Skeptical philosophers also interpreted Heraclitus in terms of their own doctrines.[31] In modern times, Heraclitus has also been seen as a process philosopher due to the influence of G.W.F. Hegel and Martin Heidegger,[31] and a potential source for understanding the Ancient Greek religion since the discovery of the Derveni papyrus.[35]

Flux and the unchanging universe of Parmenides

Parmenides of Elea, who lived around the same time as Heraclitus, espoused a doctrine of unchanging Being that has been contrasted with the constantly changing universe of Heraclitus.

It is unknown whether or not Heraclitus had any students in his lifetime.[31] Diogenes Laertius mentions an Antisthenes who wrote a commentary on Heraclitus.[lower-alpha 24] Parmenides, an Eleatic philosopher who was a near-contemporary of Heraclitus, proposed a doctrine of changelessness, which has been contrasted with the doctrine of flux put forth by Heraclitus.[36] Different philosophers have argued that either one of them may have substantially influenced each other, some taking Heraclitus to be responding to Parmenides, others that Parmenides is responding to Heraclitus, and some arguing that any direct chain of influence between the two is impossible to determine.[36] Although Heraclitus refers to older figures such as Pythagoras,[lower-alpha 25][lower-alpha 26] neither Parmenides or Heraclitus directly refer to each other in any surviving fragments, so any speculation on influence must be based on interpretations of the surviving fragments.[36]

Impermenance in Plato's Cratylus

Plato is the most famous philosopher who tried to reconcile Heraclitus and Parmenides; through Plato, both of these figures influenced virtually all subsequent Western philosophy. According to Aristotle, Plato knew of the teachings of Heraclitus through his follower Cratylus, who went a step beyond his master's doctrine and said one cannot step into the same river once[lower-alpha 27] Plato presented Cratylus as a linguistic naturalist , one who believes names must apply naturally to their objects. According to Aristotle, Cratylus took the view nothing can be said about the ever-changing world and "ended by thinking that one need not say anything, and only moved his finger".[lower-alpha 28] Cratylus may have thought continuous change warrants skepticism because one cannot define a thing that does not have a permanent nature.

Coin from c. 230 CE depicting Heraclitus as a Cynic, with club and raised hand.

Logos in Stoicism and early Christianity

The Stoics believed major tenets of their philosophy derived from the thought of Heraclitus,[37] including a commentary by Cleanthes which has not survived.[31] In surviving stoic writings, this is most evident in the writings of Marcus Aurelius.[38] Explicit connections of the earliest Stoics to Heraclitus showing how they arrived at their interpretation are missing, but they can be inferred from the Stoic fragments, which Long concludes are "modifications of Heraclitus".[39] Heraclitus states, "We should not act and speak like children of our parents", which Marcus Aurelius interpreted to mean one should not simply accept what others believe. Marcus Aurelius understood the Logos as "the account which governs everything", but Burnet cautions that these modifications of Heraclitus in the Stoic fragments make it harder to use the fragments to interpret Heraclitus himself, as the Stoics ascribed their own interpretations of terms like "logos" and "ekpyrosis" to Heraclitus.[40] The Cynics were also influenced by Heraclitus, attributing several of the later Cynic epistles to his authorship.[41]

Hippolytus of Rome, one of the early Church Fathers of the Christian Church identified Heraclitus along with the other Pre-Socratics and Academics as sources of heresy, and identified the logos as meaning the Christian "Word of God", such as in John 1:1, "In the beginning was the Word (logos) and the Word was God";[lower-alpha 29] however, modern scholars such as John Burnet viewed the relationship between Heraclitean logos and Johannine logos as fallacious, saying; "the Johannine doctrine of the logos has nothing to do with Herakleitos or with anything at all in Greek philosophy, but comes from the Hebrew Wisdom literature".[5] The Christian apologist Justin Martyr took a more positive view of Heraclitus. In his First Apology, he said both Socrates and Heraclitus were Christians before Christ: "those who lived reasonably are Christians, even though they have been thought atheists; as, among the Greeks, Socrates and Heraclitus, and men like them".[lower-alpha 30]

Dialectic in Pyrrhonic skepticism

Aenesidemus, one of the major ancient Pyrrhonist philosophers, claimed in a now-lost work that Pyrrhonism was a way to Heraclitean philosophy because Pyrrhonist practice helps one to see how opposites appear to be the case about the same thing. Once one sees this, it leads to understanding the Heraclitean view of opposites being the case about the same thing. A later Pyrrhonist philosopher, Sextus Empiricus, disagreed, arguing opposites' appearing to be the case about the same thing is not a dogma of the Pyrrhonists but a matter occurring to the Pyrrhonists, to the other philosophers, and to all of humanity.[lower-alpha 31]

Donato Bramante painted Heraclitus and Democritus and the Weeping and Laughing philospher motif

Weeping philosopher

In Lucian of Samosata's "Philosophies for Sale,"[lower-alpha 32] Heraclitus is auctioned off as the "weeping philosopher" alongside Democritus, who is known as the "laughing philosopher" part of the weeping and laughing philosopher motif. This pairing, which may have originated with the Cynic philosopher Menippus,[42] has been portrayed several times in renaissance art, where it generally references their reactions to the folly of mankind.[43] Heraclitus also appears in Raphael's School of Athens.

Modern Reception

Heraclitus has been the subject of numerous interpretations. According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Heraclitus has been seen as a "material monist or a process philosopher; a scientific cosmologist, a metaphysician and a religious thinker; an empiricist, a rationalist, a mystic; a conventional thinker and a revolutionary; a developer of logic — one who denied the law of non-contradiction; the first genuine philosopher and an anti-intellectual obscurantist."[1] G.W.F. Hegel interpreted Heraclitus as a process philosopher, seeing the "becoming" in Heraclitus as a natural result of the ontology of "being" and "non-being" in Parmenides.[1] Martin Heidegger was also influenced by Heraclitus, as seen in his Introduction to Metaphysics. Heidegger believed that the thinking of Heraclitus and Parmenides was the origin of philosophy and misunderstood by Plato and Aristotle, leading all of Western philosophy astray.[44]

Notes

Explanatory Notes

  1. West suggests that the beginning may be tentatively[7] ordered as follows:[7] B1, B114, B2, B89, B30,B31,B90,B60

Fragment Numbers

  1. (DK B121)
  2. Laërtius ix.1-15
  3. (DK 22B40)
  4. Laërtius 1-15
  5. Laërtius ix.1-15
  6. Laërtius ix.1-15
  7. B1, Against the Mathematicians 7.132
  8. Laërtius ix.1-15
  9. Rhetoric 3.1407b11
  10. Laërtius ix.1-15
  11. Laërtius
  12. De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, Chapter 2, Section 15.
  13. Laërtius
  14. Eudemian Ethics 1235a25
  15. Plato, Cratylus, 509a (DK 22A7)
  16. "On those who step into the same rivers, different and different waters flow" - Arius Didymus, quoted in Stobaeus (DK B12)
    "We both step and do not step into the same, we both are and are not" - Heraclitus (commentator), Homeric Allegories (DK B49a)
    "It is not possible to step into the same river twice" - Plutarch, On the E at Delphi (DK B91)
  17. (DK 22 B49a)
  18. Clement, Stromtaeis (DK B30)
  19. (DK 22B50)
  20. (DK B19)
  21. lit:word, speech, discourse
  22. (DK 22C1)
  23. (DK 22C2)
  24. Diogenes Laërtius, Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 9.15
  25. Laërtius
  26. DK B129
  27. Metaphysics, 987a32
  28. Metaphysics Books 4, section 1010a
  29. Hippolytus Book IX, Chapter 4-5
  30. Justin Martyr
  31. Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I, Chapter 29, Sections 210–211
  32. (DK 22C5)

Citations

  1. Graham 2019.
  2. Kahn 1979, p. 1-3.
  3. Burnet 1892, p. 130.
  4. Kirk 1954, p. 1.
  5. Burnet 1892, p. 133.
  6. Burnet 1892, p. 132.
  7. West 1971, p. 113-117.
  8. McCabe 2015.
  9. Kahn 1979, p. 168.
  10. Kahn 1979.
  11. Kahn 1979, p. 5.
  12. Mansfield 1999, p. 39.
  13. Graham 2008, p. 175.
  14. Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Graham 2008, pp. 175–177.
  15. Sandywell 1996, pp. 263–265; Curd 2020, Xenophanes of Colophon and Heraclitus of Ephesus.
  16. Guthrie 1962, p. 46.
  17. Barnes 1982, p. 49.
  18. Dietz, Karl-Martin (2004). Heraklit von Ephesus und die Entwicklung der Individualität. Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben. p. 60. ISBN 978-3772512735.
  19. Warren 2014, pp. 72–74.
  20. West 1971, p. 172-173.
  21. Hussey 1999, p. 111.
  22. Graham 2008, pp. 170–172.
  23. West 1971, p. 170-171.
  24. West 1971, p. 174-175.
  25. West 1971, p. 170-176.
  26. Warren 2014, p. 63; Sandywell 1996, p. 237.
  27. Warren 2014, p. 63.
  28. West 1971, p. 124-125.
  29. Guthrie 1962, p. 419.
  30. Wheelwright 1959, p. 69-73.
  31. Graham 2019, §7.
  32. Graham 2002.
  33. Nehamas 2002.
  34. "Structural Logos in Heraclitus and the Sophists".
  35. Betegh 2004.
  36. Graham 2002, p. 27-30.
  37. Long 2001, chapter 2.
  38. Long 2001, p. 56.
  39. Long 2001, p. 51.
  40. Burnet 1892, pp. 142–143.
  41. J. F. Kindstrand, “The Cynics and Heraclitus”, Eranos 82 (1984), 149–78
  42. Laughing and Weeping Melancholy: Democritus and Heraclitus as Emblems | SpringerLink
  43. "Heraclitus, Hendrick ter Brugghen, 1628". Rijksmuseum.
  44. W. Julian Korab-Karpowicz, The Presocratics in the Thought of Martin Heidegger (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2016), page 58.

References

Ancient Testimony

In the Diels-Kranz numbering for testimony and fragments of Pre-Socratic philosophy, Heraclitus is catalogued as number 22. The most recent edition of this catalogue is

Life and Doctrines

Fragments

Imitation

  • C1. Hippocrates (1931). On Regimen. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. IV. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • C2. Hippocrates (1923). On Nutrition. Hippocrates Collected Works. Vol. I. Translated by W. H. S. Jones. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • C4. Cleanthes. Hymn to Zeus. fr. 537.
  • C5. Lucian (1905). Philosophies for Sale. The works of Lucian of Samosata. Vol. 1. Translated by Fowler, H. W.; Fowler, F. G.

Modern Scholarship

  • Barnes, Jonathan (1982). "The Natural Philosophy of Heraclitus". The Presocratic Philosophers. London & New York: Routledge Taylor & Francis Group. pp. 43–62. ISBN 978-0-415-05079-1.
  • Betegh, Gábor (2004). The Derveni papyrus : cosmology, theology, and interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780511584435.
  • Burnet, John (1892). "Heraclitus". Early Greek Philosophy. A. and C. Black. Retrieved 5 March 2022.
  • Curd, Patricia (2020). "Presocratic philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Graham, D. W. (2008). "Heraclitus: Flux, Order, and Knowledge". In Curd, P.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 169–188. ISBN 978-0-19-514687-5.
  • Graham, D. W. (2002). "Heraclitus and Parmenides". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 27–44. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
  • Graham, Daniel W. (2019). "Heraclitus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962). A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hussey, Edward (1999). "Heraclitus". In Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 88–112. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
  • Kahn, Charles H. (1979). The Art and Thought of Heraclitus. An Edition of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-21883-2.
  • Kirk, G. S. (1954). Heraclitus, the Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Long, A. A. (2001). Stoic Studies. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-22974-7.
  • Mansfield, Jaap (1999). Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 22–45. ISBN 978-0-521-44667-9.
  • McCabe, Mary Margaret (2015-05-01), "Platonic Conversations", Oxford University Press, pp. 1–31, doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198732884.003.0001, ISBN 978-0-19-873288-4 {{citation}}: Missing or empty |title= (help)
  • Nehamas, Alexander (2002). "Parminidean Being/Heraclitean Fire". In Caston, V.; Graham, D. W. (eds.). Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate. pp. 45–64. ISBN 978-0-7546-0502-7.
  • Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse c. 600-450 B.C.: Logological Investigations: Volume Three. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-85347-2.
  • Warren, James (5 December 2014). Presocratics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-49337-2.
  • West, Martin L. (1971). Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Clarendon Press. Retrieved 6 March 2022. Chapters 4-6 deal with Heraclitus

Further reading

This article is issued from Wikipedia. The text is licensed under Creative Commons - Attribution - Sharealike. Additional terms may apply for the media files.