History of philosophy
The history of philosophy is the systematic study of the development of philosophical thought. It focuses on philosophy as rational inquiry based on argumentation but some theorists also include myths, religious traditions, and proverbial lore.
Western philosophy originated with an inquiry into the fundamental nature of the cosmos in Ancient Greece. Subsequent philosophical developments covered a wide range of topics including the nature of reality and the mind, how people should act, and how to arrive at knowledge. The following medieval period was focused more on theology. The Renaissance period saw a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism. The modern period was characterized by an increased focus on how philosophical and scientific knowledge is created. Its new ideas were used in the Enlightenment period to challenge traditional authorities. Influential developments in the 19th and 20th centuries were German idealism, pragmatism, positivism, formal logic, linguistic analysis, phenomenology, existentialism, and postmodernism.
Arabic-Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophers. It had its peak period during the Islamic Golden Age. One of its topics was the relation between reason and revelation as two compatible ways of arriving at the truth. Avicenna developed a comprehensive philosophical system that synthesized Islamic faith and Greek philosophy. After the Islamic Golden Age, the influence of philosophical inquiry waned, partly due to Al-Ghazali's critique of philosophy. In the 17th century, Mulla Sadra developed a metaphysical system based on mysticism. Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries as an attempt to reconcile traditional Islamic doctrines with modernity.
Indian philosophy is characterized by its combined interest in the nature of reality, the ways of arriving at knowledge, and the spiritual question of how to reach enlightenment. Its roots are the religious scriptures known as the Vedas. Subsequent Indian philosophy is often divided into orthodox schools, which are closely associated with the teachings of the Vedas, and heterodox schools, like Buddhism and Jainism. Influential schools based on them were the Hindu schools of Advaita Vedanta and Navya-Nyāya as well as the Buddhist schools of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra. In the modern period, the exchange between Indian and Western thought led various Indian philosophers to develop comprehensive systems. They aimed to unite and harmonize diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought.
Central topics in Chinese philosophy were right social conduct, government, and self-cultivation. In early Chinese philosophy, Confucianism explored moral virtues and how they lead to harmony in society while Daoism focused on the relation between humans and nature. Later developments include the introduction and transformation of Buddhist teachings and the emergence of the schools of Xuanxue and Neo-Confucianism. The modern period in Chinese philosophy was characterized by its encounter with Western philosophy, specifically with Marxism. Other influential traditions in the history of philosophy were Japanese philosophy, Latin American philosophy, and African philosophy.
Definition and related disciplines
The history of philosophy is the field of inquiry that studies the historical development of philosophical thought. It aims to provide a systematic and chronological exposition of philosophical concepts and doctrines as well as the philosophers that conceived them and the schools of thought they belong to. It is not a mere collection of theories but tries to show how the different theories are related to each other. For example, some schools of thought build on earlier theories while others reject them and try to provide alternative explanations.[1][2][3] Purely mystical and religious traditions are often excluded from the history of philosophy if their claims are not based on rational inquiry and argumentation. But some theorists treat the topic in a very wide sense to include the philosophical aspects of traditional worldviews, religious myths, and proverbial lore.[4]
The history of philosophy has both a historical and a philosophical component. The historical component is concerned with how philosophical thought unfolded throughout the ages. It asks which philosophers held what views and how they were influenced by their social and cultural context. The philosophical component concerns whether the studied theories are true. It reflects on the arguments presented for the positions and assesses their validity and hidden assumptions. It makes the philosophical heritage accessible to a contemporary audience and evaluates its continued relevance today. Some historians of philosophy focus primarily on the historical component. They hold that the history of philosophy is part of the wider discipline known as intellectual history. Other theorists put more emphasis on the philosophical component. They tend to claim that the history of philosophy goes beyond intellectual history because its interest is not exclusively historical.[5]
Closely related to the history of philosophy is the historiography of philosophy. The historiography of philosophy examines what methods historians of philosophy use. It is also interested in how the dominant opinions in this field changed.[6][7][8] Different methods and approaches are used to study the history of philosophy. Some historians are mainly interested in philosophical theories and less in the fact that they were formulated in the past. They focus not on how the different positions evolved through time but on what claims they made and how they are still of interest. A different approach is to see the history of philosophy as an evolution. This approach is based on the assumption that there is a clear progress from one period to the next. In this process, earlier theories are refined or replaced by more advanced later theories. Other historians try to understand past philosophical theories as a product of their time. Their interest is in what positions past philosophers accepted and why they did so. The relevance of these positions for today is not their focus. They study, among other things, how the historical context and the philosopher's biography shaped their philosophical outlook.[9]
Another important methodological feature is the use of periodization. It consists in splitting the history of philosophy into distinct periods. Each period corresponds to one or several philosophical tendencies prevalent during that historical timeframe.[10] Traditionally, treatments of the history of philosophy often focused primarily on Western philosophy. But in a wider sense, it includes many non-Western traditions like Arabic-Persian philosophy, Indian philosophy, and Chinese philosophy.[11][12][13]
Western
Western philosophy covers the philosophy associated with the geographical region and cultural heritage of the Western world. It started in Ancient Greece and then shifted to the Roman Empire. It later spread to Western Europe and eventually to many other regions, including North America, Latin America, and Australia. It spans over 2.5 millennia, starting in the 6th century BCE and continuing until the present day.[14][15][16]
Ancient
Western philosophy originated in Ancient Greece in the 6th century BCE. This period ended by convention in 529 CE when the Platonic Academy and other philosophical schools in Athens were forced to shut down to stop their non-Christian doctrines.[17][18][19]
Presocratic
The first period of Ancient Greek philosophy is called Presocratic philosophy and lasted until about the mid-4th century BCE. The study of Presocratic philosophy is often difficult because many of the texts only survived in fragments and often have to be studied indirectly based on quotations found in other texts.[19][20]
A key innovation of Presocratic philosophy was its attempt to provide rational explanations of the cosmos as a whole. This was in contrast to commonly-held Greek mythology, which provided theological interpretations – such as the myth of Uranus and Gaia – to emphasize the role of various gods and goddesses who would continue to be worshipped even as Greek philosophy developed across the centuries. The Presocratic philosophers became some of the first to reject Greek theology, instead seeking in its place to provide empirical theories explaining how the world came to be and why it functions the way it does.[19][20][21]
Thales, (c.624–545 BCE) who is usually seen as the very first philosopher, sought to describe the cosmos in terms of a first principle, or arche, which was the primal source of all things, and suggested that water was this arche. Anaximander (c.610–545 BCE) gave a more abstract explanation, arguing that the eternal substance responsible for the creation of the world lies beyond the world of human perception. He called his arche the apeiron, meaning "the boundless".[19][22]
Heraclitus (c.540–480 BCE) saw a world where everything is in constant flux. This is exemplified in his famous statement that it is impossible to step into the same river twice. He also emphasized the role of logos as an order that governs both the inner self and the outer world.[23][24] Parmenides (c.515–450 BCE) rejected this emphasis on flux, claiming that true reality is unchanging, eternal, and indivisible. Parmenides' student Zeno of Elea (c.490–430 BCE) formulated various paradoxes in support of this idea, arguing that motion was an illusion and change was impossible. One paradox argues that it is impossible for the fast Achilles to overtake the slower tortoise.[25]
Another influential theory was the atomism of Democritus (c.460–370 BCE), which states that reality is made up of many indivisible particles called atoms.[26][27] Further Presocratic philosophers are Anaximenes, Pythagoras, Xenophanes, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Leucippus, and the sophists, such as Protagoras and Gorgias.[19]
Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle
The philosophy of Socrates (469–399 BCE) and Plato (427–347 BCE) built on Presocratic philosophy but also changed the philosophical focus in many ways. Socrates did not write anything and owes his influence to the impact he made on his contemporaries. This concerns specifically his way to conduct philosophical inquiries in the form of so-called Socratic dialogues. They often start with simple questions in an attempt to explore a topic and critically reflect on underlying ideas and assumptions. In contrast to the Presocratics, his focus was less on metaphysical theories and more on moral philosophy. In many of his dialogues, he explored the question of what it means to lead a good life, by exploring virtues, like justice, courage, and wisdom. Despite being regarded as a great teacher of ethics, Socrates did not typically teach any specific moral doctrines. Instead, he tried to prompt his audience to think for themselves and become aware of their ignorance.[28][29][30]
Most of what is known of Socrates comes from the writings of his student Plato. Plato's works take the form of dialogues between other philosophers. This makes it difficult to reconstruct which of his doctrines are his own theories. He articulated the theory of forms, which claims that the true nature of reality is found in abstract and eternal forms or ideas. Examples are the forms of beauty, justice, and goodness. The physical and changeable world of the senses, on the other hand, is only an imperfect copy of the forms. The theory of forms shaped subsequent views of metaphysics and epistemology to this day. Plato can also be regarded as a pioneer in the field of psychology. He divided the soul into three faculties: reason, spirit, and desire, which are responsible for different mental phenomena and interact with each other in many ways. Other contributions of Plato concern the fields of ethics and political philosophy.[31][32][33] Plato also founded his Academy, which is sometimes considered the first institute of higher education.[34][35]
Aristotle (384–322 BCE), who was initially a student at Plato's Academy, was a systematic philosopher. His teachings have been transcribed in the form of treatises on various subjects in the philosophy of nature, metaphysics, logic, and ethics. He introduced many technical terms in these fields that are still used today. He accepted Plato's distinction between form and matter, but he rejected the idea that forms can exist by themselves and claimed instead that forms and matter depend on each other. This issue was discussed by many subsequent philosophers as the problem of universals. In the field of metaphysics, he presented a set of basic categories of being as a framework for classifying and analyzing the different aspects of being. He also proposed his so-called four causes, which aim to explain why any movement or change in nature happens. According to the teleological cause, for example, everything in nature has a goal and moves towards it. Aristotle's ethical theory holds that to lead a good life, a person needs to cultivate virtues in order to flourish. In the field of logic, Aristotle codified rules of correct inferences.[36]
Hellenistic and Roman
Ancient philosophy after Aristotle was marked by the emergence of wider philosophical movements, like Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Skepticism, the so-called Hellenistic schools of thought. Their inquiry focused on fields like ethics, physics, logic, and epistemology. This period began with the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BCE and had its main impact until the end of the Roman Republic in 31 BCE.[37][38]
The Epicureans accepted and refined Democritus's idea that nature is composed of indivisible atoms. In the field of ethics, they saw pleasure as the highest good but rejected the idea that luxury and indulging in sensory pleasures lead to long-term happiness. Instead, they argued that a nuanced form of hedonism, a simple life characterized by tranquillity, was the best way to achieve this.[39][40][41]
The Stoics denied this hedonistic outlook; they saw desires and aversions as obstacles to their goal of living in tune with reason and virtue. In order to transcend or overcome these desires, they advocated self-mastery and an attitude of indifference.[42]
The skeptics explored the question of how judgments and opinions affect well-being. They claimed that dogmatic beliefs cause emotional disturbances. They recommended that people suspend judgments for issues where certainty is not possible. According to some skeptics, this applies to all beliefs and any form of knowledge is impossible.[43]
The school of Neoplatonism belongs to the later part of the ancient period. It started in the 3rd century CE and had its peak period until the 6th century CE. It inherited many ideas from Plato and Aristotle and transformed them in creative ways. Its core idea is that there is a transcendent and ineffable entity responsible for all existence. It is simply called "the One" or "the Good". The Intellect emerges from the One and contemplates it. This in turn gives rise to the Soul, which generates the material world. Influential Neoplatonists were Plotinus (204–270 CE) and his student Porphyry (234–305 CE).[44]
Medieval
The medieval period in Western philosophy started between 400 and 500 CE and ended between 1400 and 1500 CE.[45] One of its core differences from earlier philosophers is its focus on religious thought. The Christian Emperor Justinian forced schools of philosophy, such as Plato's Academy, to close. Intellectual activity was centralized in the Church and departing from doctrinal orthodoxy carried many risks. For these reasons, some consider it a "dark age" in comparison to what came before and after it.[46][47] Central topics in this period were the problem of universals, the nature of God, proofs of the existence of God, and the relation between reason and faith. The early medieval period was particularly shaped by Plato's philosophy while Aristotelian ideas became dominant in its later parts.[48]
Augustine of Hippo (354–430 CE) was influenced by Platonism and used this perspective to explain the key concepts and problems of the Christian doctrine. He accepted the Neoplatonist idea that God or the ultimate source is both good and incomprehensible. This prompted him to address the problem of evil, i.e. to explain how evil could exist in a world created by a benevolent, all-knowing, and all-powerful God. His explanation is that God gave humans free will. This enables them to do good and evil together with the responsibility for their choice. Further influential ideas of Augustine were his arguments for the existence of God, his theory of time, and his just war theory.[49][50][51]
Boethius (477–524 CE) had a keen interest in Greek philosophy. He translated many of Aristotle's works and tried to integrate and reconcile them with Christian doctrine. He discussed the problem of universals and formulated a theory to harmonize Plato's and Aristotle's views. He tried to achieve this by claiming that universals exist in the mind without matter in one way. But they also exist in material objects in another way. This idea was influential in the subsequent medieval debate on the problem of universals: it inspired so-called nominalists to claim that universals exist only in the mind. In relation to the Christian doctrine, Boethius explored the problem of the trinity, i.e. the question of how God can exist in three persons at the same time as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit.[52]
Scholasticism
The later part of the medieval period was dominated by scholasticism. Scholasticism was strongly influenced by Aristotelian philosophy and followed a systematic and methodological approach.[53][54][55] Responsible for this intensified interest in Aristotle was the Arabic-Persian tradition. It preserved, translated, and interpreted many works of Aristotle that were lost in the Western world.[56][57][58]
Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109 CE) is often considered the father of scholasticism. He saw reason and faith as two complementary aspects that depend on each other to arrive at a proper understanding. He is most well-known for his ontological argument for the existence of God. He defined God as the greatest conceivable being and argued that God must exist outside his mind. This is based on the idea that God would not be the greatest conceivable being if He only existed in the mind.[59][60][61] Peter Abelard (1079–1142) also emphasized the harmony between reason and faith. He claimed that both emerge from the same divine source. For this reason, he concluded that there cannot be a contradiction between them. Another influential innovation was his nominalism, which claimed that universals exist only as mental constructs.[53][62]
Thomas Aquinas (1224–1274 CE) is often seen as the most influential medieval philosopher. Rooted in Aristotelianism, he developed a comprehensive system of scholastic philosophy. It covered areas like metaphysics, theology, ethics, and political theory. Many of his insights were summarized in his work Summa Theologiae. A key goal in most of his writings was to show how faith and reason work in harmony. He held that reason supports and reinforces the Christian tenets. But faith in God's revelation is still necessary since reason is unable to understand everything by itself. This concerns, for example, the claim that the world is eternal and the details of how God is related to His creation. In metaphysics, Thomas claimed that any entity is characterized by two aspects: essence and existence. Understanding a thing involves grasping its essence. This can happen without perceiving whether it exists. God constitutes a special case: His existence is unrestricted and is identical to his essence.[63][64][65] In ethics, Thomas held that moral principles are rooted in human nature. He thought that ethics is about doing what is good and that humans, as rational beings, have a natural inclination to pursue the Good.[66][67] In natural theology, his famous Five Ways are five arguments for the existence of God.[68][69]
Duns Scotus (1266–1308 CE) engaged with many of Thomas's ideas. In metaphysics, he rejected the claim that there is a real distinction between essence and existence. He held instead that this is only a formal distinction. This means that essence and existence are two different aspects of a thing. But they cannot be separated. He further claimed that there is a unique essence for each individual entity. This unique essence, called haecceity, is what makes an entity distinct from other entities of the same kind.[70][71][72]
William of Ockham (1285–1347 CE) is one of the last scholastic philosophers. He is the inventor of the methodological principle known as Ockham's Razor. This principle is used to choose between competing explanations of the same phenomenon. It states that simple explanations are to be preferred. In this context, an explanation is simpler if it assumes the existence of fewer entities. Ockham used the principle to argue for nominalism and against realism about universals. According to him, nominalism is the simpler explanation since it does not assume that universals exist.[73][74]
Renaissance
The Renaissance period started in the middle of the 14th century and lasted until the beginning of the 17th century. This movement had its roots in Italy and gradually expanded to other regions of Western Europe. Some of its key aspects were a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism. It also saw a shift toward scientific inquiry. This was a significant departure from the medieval period with its main focus on religious and scholastic traditions. A further change was that intellectual activity was not as closely tied to the Church as before: most scholars in this period were not clerics.[75]
An important part of the resurgence of Ancient Greek philosophy concerned a revived enthusiasm for the teachings of Plato. This Renaissance Platonism was still conducted on the background of Christian theology and often tried to show how Plato's philosophy is compatible with and can be applied to Christian doctrines. For example, Marsilio Ficino (1433–1499) argued that souls establish the connection between the realm of Platonic forms and the sensory realm. According to Plato, love can be understood as a ladder to reach higher forms of understanding. Ficino interpreted this in an intellectual sense as a way of relating to God through the love of knowledge.[76][77][78]
The revival of Ancient Greek philosophy was not restricted to Platonism. It encompassed other schools as well, such as Skepticism, Epicureanism, and Stoicism.[79] It was closely associated with the emergence of Renaissance humanism. Renaissance humanism is a human-centred worldview that highly values the academic disciplines studying human society and culture. This also included a shift in perspective by seeing humans as genuine individuals. Renaissance humanism was not primarily a philosophical movement. But it brought about many social and cultural changes that affected philosophical activity.[80] These changes were also accompanied by an increased interest in political philosophy. Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) argued that a key responsibility of rulers is to ensure stability and security. They should govern effectively to benefit the state as a whole, even if harsh circumstances require the use of force and ruthless action. A different political outlook was presented by Thomas More (1478–1535). He envisioned an ideal society that is characterized by communal ownership, egalitarianism, and devotion to public service.[81][82][83]
The Renaissance also saw various developments in the philosophy of nature and science, which helped prepare the scientific revolution. One of them concerned the emphasis on empirical observation for scientific inquiry. Another was the idea that mathematical explanations should be employed to understand those observations.[81] Francis Bacon (1561–1626 CE) is often seen as a transitional figure between the Renaissance and modernity. He tried to revolutionize logic and scientific inquiry with his Novum Organum, which was meant to replace Aristotle's influential work in this field. It discussed, for example, the role of inductive reasoning for empirical inquiry to arrive at general laws from many individual observations.[84][85] Another transitional figure is Galileo Galilei (1564–1642 CE). He played a key role in the Copernican Revolution by claiming that the Sun, and not the Earth, is at the center of the Solar System. [81][86][87]
Early modern
Early modern philosophy encompasses the 17th and 18th centuries. The philosophers in this period are traditionally divided into empiricists and rationalists. However, contemporary historians have argued that this is not a strict dichotomy and more a matter of varying degrees. These schools have in common that they seek a clearly established, rigorous, and systematic method of inquiry. This philosophical focus on method reflected the advances happening simultaneously as part of the scientific revolution. Empiricism and rationalism differ concerning the type of method they promote. Empiricism focuses on sensory experience. Rationalism emphasizes reason – particularly the principles of non-contradiction and sufficient reason – and innate knowledge. This focus on method was already foreshadowed in Renaissance thought but only came to full prominence in the early modern period. The second half of this period saw the emergence of the Enlightenment movement. It used these advances to challenge traditional authorities while promoting progress, individual freedom, and human rights.[88]
Empiricism
Empiricism in the early modern period was mainly associated with British philosophy. John Locke (1632–1704) is sometimes considered the father of empiricism. In his book An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, he rejected the idea of innate knowledge and claimed that knowledge is empirical. He held that the mind is a blank slate that depends on sensory experience to acquire ideas. He distinguished between primary qualities, which belong to external objects independent of observers, and secondary qualities, which are the powers of objects to cause sensations in observers.[89] George Berkeley (1685–1753) was strongly influenced by Locke. He proposed a different and more radical form of empiricism. He developed a form of idealism by giving primacy to perceptions and ideas over material things. He argued that objects exist only to the extent that they are perceived by the mind. This implies that there is no reality outside the mind.[90] [91]
David Hume (1711–1776) also accepted the basic empiricist tenet that knowledge is derived from sensory experience. He concluded from this idea that it is not possible to know that one thing caused another thing. His reason for this view was that the relation between cause and effect is not perceptible. Instead, he argued that the mind only perceives regular patterns between earlier and later phenomena. This leads it into a habit of expecting a phenomenon to occur because another one just occurred.[92][93][94] The empiricism promoted by Hume and others had an important influence on the scientific method. This concerned specifically the focus on observation, experimentation, and rigorous testing.[95][96]
Rationalism
Another dominant school of thought in this period was rationalism. René Descartes (1596–1650) had a pivotal role in its emergence. He aimed to arrive at absolutely certain knowledge. To do so, he employed methodological doubt by questioning all his beliefs to find an indubitable foundation of knowledge. He encountered this foundation in the claim "I think, therefore I am". He employed various rationalist principles, such as the focus on deductive reasoning, to develop a comprehensive philosophical system based on this foundation. It is based on substance dualism and claims that body and mind are independent entities that coexist.[97][98]
The rationalist philosophy of Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) gave even more emphasis to the role of deductive reasoning. He developed and used the so-called geometrical method to create his philosophical system. It starts with a small set of self-evident axioms. It proceeds by inferring a comprehensive philosophical system from them by using deductive reasoning. In contrast to Descartes, Spinoza arrived at a metaphysical monism.[99][100] Another influential rationalist was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716). His principle of sufficient reason states that everything has a reason. He used this principle to develop his metaphysical system called monadology.[101][102]
Enlightenment and other late modern philosophy
The later half of the early modern period saw the emergence of the cultural and intellectual movement known as the Enlightenment. It employed tendencies of both empiricism and rationalism to challenge traditional authorities and promote the pursuit of knowledge. It advocated individual freedom and had an optimistic outlook toward progress and the improvement of society.[103][104] Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was one of the central thinkers of the Enlightenment. He emphasized reason as a tool to understand the world and used it to criticize dogmatism and blind adherence to authority. He provided a comprehensive philosophical system to synthesize both empiricism and rationalism. His transcendental idealism explored how the mind and its pre-established categories shape human experience of reality. In ethics, he developed a deontological moral system that is based on universal moral duties.[105][106] Other important Enlightenment philosophers were Voltaire (1694–1778), Montesquieu (1689–1755), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).[103][107]
Political philosophy in this period was shaped by the book Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679). Hobbes had a negative opinion of the natural state of humans and argued that it involves a war of everyone against everyone. The reason and purpose of civil society is to avoid this state. This happens through a social contract in which everyone cedes some of their rights to a central and immensely powerful authority to protect them from external dangers.[108][109] Rousseau also theorized political life on the model of a contract. His political outlook, however, was quite different because of his more positive assessment of human nature. This led him to argue in favor of democracy.[110][111]
19th century
The 19th century was a rich and diverse period in philosophy. In it, the term "philosophy" acquired the distinctive meaning used today as a discipline that is distinct from the empirical sciences and mathematics. A rough division between two types of philosophical approaches in this period can be drawn. Some philosophers tried to provide comprehensive and all-inclusive systems, like the German and British idealists. Another approach seen in Bentham, Mill, and the American pragmatists was the focus on more specific questions pertaining to particular fields, such as ethics and epistemology.[112][113][114]
German idealism was among the most influential philosophical schools in this period. This tradition was inaugurated by Immanuel Kant, who argued that the conceptual activity of the subject is always partially constitutive of experience and knowledge. Subsequent German idealists objected to what they saw as theoretical problems with Kant's dualisms and the contradictory status of the thing-in-itself.[115][116][117] They sought a single unifying principle as the foundation of all reality. According to Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814), this principle is the activity of the subject or transcendental ego, which posits both itself and its opposite. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775–1854) rejected this focus on the ego. He sought a more abstract principle, referred to as the absolute or the world-soul, to act as the foundation of both consciousness and nature.[118]
The philosophy of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) is often described as the culmination of this tradition.[119][120][121] Hegel reconstructed a philosophical history according to which the measure of progress is the actualization of freedom. He did this not only with respect to political life, but also with respect to philosophy, the aim of which, he claimed, is a form of self-knowledge characterized by the identity of subject and object. His term for this is "the absolute" because such knowledge – which occurs in art, religion, and philosophy – is entirely self-conditioned.[122][123][124]
Further influential currents of thought in this period were historicism and neo-Kantianism. Historicists such as Johann Gottfried Herder emphasized the validity and unique nature of historical knowledge of individual events in contrast to universal knowledge of eternal truths. Neo-Kantianism was a diverse philosophical movement that revived and reinterpreted Kant's ideas.[125]
British idealism developed later in the 19th century and was strongly influenced by Hegel. For example, Francis Herbert Bradley (1846–1924) argued that reality is an all-inclusive totality of being that is identified with absolute spirit. He is also famous for claiming that external relations do not exist.[126][127]
Karl Marx (1818–1883) was another philosopher inspired by Hegel's ideas. He applied them to the historical development of society based on class struggles. But he rejected the idealistic outlook in the formulation of his dialectical materialism. For him, economy rather than spirit was the basic force behind historical development.[128][129]
According to Arthur Schopenhauer, the underlying principle of all reality is the will, which he saw as an irrational and blind force. Influenced by Indian philosophy, he formed a pessimistic outlook by coming to the conclusion that the expressions of the will ultimately lead to suffering.[130] He had a profound influence on Friedrich Nietzsche, who saw the will to power as a fundamental driving force in nature. He used this concept to criticize many religious and philosophical ideas: he saw them as disguised attempts to wield power rather than pure spiritual achievements.[131]
In the field of ethics, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) developed his philosophy of utilitarianism. It states that whether an action is right depends on its utility, i.e., on the pleasure and pain it causes. The goal of actions is to maximize happiness or to produce "the greatest good for the greatest number". His student John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) became one of the foremost proponents of utilitarianism. He further refined the theory by claiming that what matters is not just the degree of pleasure and pain, but also their type or quality.[132][133]
Toward the end of the 19th century, the philosophy of pragmatism emerged in the United States. Pragmatists evaluate philosophical ideas by how useful and effective they are at guiding action. Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) is usually considered the founder of pragmatism. He held that the meaning of ideas and theories lies in their practical and observable consequences. According to this view, to say that an object is hard just means that, on a practical level, it is difficult to break, pierce, or scratch this object. He held that a true belief is a stable belief that works even if it has to be revised in the future. His pragmatist philosophy reached a wider popularity thanks to his life-long friend William James (1842–1910). James applied Peirce's ideas to psychology. He argued, for example, that the meaning of an idea consists in its experiential consequences. He rejected the claim that experiences are isolated events and talked instead of a stream of consciousness.[134][135]
20th century
Philosophy in the 20th century is usually divided into two main traditions: analytic philosophy and continental philosophy.[lower-alpha 1] Analytic philosophy was dominant in English-speaking countries. It emphasizes the importance of clarity and precise language. It often employs tools like formal logic and linguistic analysis to examine traditional philosophical problems in the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, science, and ethics. Continental philosophy was more prominent in European countries, particularly in Germany and France. It is used as an umbrella term without a precisely established meaning. It covers philosophical movements like phenomenology, hermeneutics, existentialism, deconstruction, critical theory, and psychoanalytic theory.[138][139] Interest in academic philosophy increased rapidly in the 20th century in terms of the number of philosophical publications and of philosophers working at academic institutions.[140] Another change in this period was the increased presence of female philosophers. However, despite this improvement, they remained underrepresented.[141]
Some schools of thought in 20th-century philosophy do not clearly fall into either analytic or continental philosophy. Pragmatism further evolved from its 19th-century roots thanks to scholars like Richard Rorty (1931–2007) and Hilary Putnam (1926–2016). It was applied to new fields of inquiry, such as epistemology, politics, education, and the social sciences.[142] Philosophy in the 20th century also saw the rise of feminism, which studies and criticizes traditional assumptions and power structures that disadvantage women.[143][144]
Analytic
George Edward Moore (1873–1958) was one of the founding figures of analytic philosophy. He emphasized the importance of common sense and used it to argue against radical forms of skepticism. He was particularly influential in the field of ethics, where he claimed that our actions should promote the good. He held that the concept "good" cannot be defined in terms of other concepts. According to him, whether something is good can be known through intuition.[145][146][147]
Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) was another pioneer of the analytic tradition. His development of modern symbolic logic had a significant impact on subsequent philosophers even outside the field of logic. He employed these advances in his attempt to prove that arithmetic can be reduced to logic. This thesis is known as logicism.[148][140][149] The logicist project of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) was even more ambitious since it included not only arithmetic but also geometry and analysis. Their attempts were very fruitful but did not fully succeed since additional axioms, besides the axioms of logic, are required. In the philosophy of language, Russell's theory of definite descriptions was influential. It explains how to make sense of paradoxical expressions like "the present King of France", which do not refer to any entity.[150][151] He developed the theory of logical atomism, which was further refined by his student Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). According to Wittgenstein's early philosophy, the world is made up of a multitude of atomic facts. The world and language have the same logical structure, which is why it is possible to represent these facts using propositions. Despite the influence of this theory, Wittgenstein came to reject it in his later philosophy. He argued instead that language consists of a variety of games, each with its own rules and conventions. According to this view, meaning is determined by usage and not by referring to facts.[152][153]
Logical positivism developed in parallel and was strongly influenced by empiricism. It is primarily associated with the Vienna Circle and focused on logical analysis and empirical verification. One of its members was Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970). He defended the verification principle, which claims that a statement is meaningless if it cannot be verified through sensory experience or the laws of logic. He used this principle to reject the discipline of metaphysics in general.[154][155] This principle was criticized by Carnap's student Willard Van Orman Quine (1908–2000) as one of the dogmas of empiricism. One of the core ideas of Quine's philosophy was naturalism, which he understood as the claim that the natural sciences provide the most reliable framework for understanding the world. He used this outlook to argue that mathematical entities have real existence because they are indispensable to science.[156][157][158]
Wittgenstein's later philosophy formed part of ordinary language philosophy, which analyzed everyday language to understand philosophical concepts and problems. The theory of speech acts by John Langshaw Austin (1911–1960) was an influential early contribution to this field. Other theorists in this tradition were Gilbert Ryle (1900–1976) and Sir Peter Frederick Strawson (1919–2006). The shift in emphasis on the role of language is known as the linguistic turn.[159][160]
Richard Mervyn Hare (1919–2002) and John Leslie Mackie (1917–1981) were influential ethical philosophers in the analytic tradition. John Rawls (1921–2002) and Robert Nozick (1938–2002) made significant contributions to political philosophy.[161][162][163]
Continental
In the tradition of continental philosophy, phenomenology was an important early movement. It tried to give an unprejudiced description of human experience from a subjective perspective. It used this description as a method to analyze and evaluate philosophical problems belonging to diverse fields like epistemology, ontology, philosophy of mind, and ethics. Its founder was Edmund Husserl (1859–1938). He emphasized the importance of suspending all antecedent beliefs to give a pure and unbiased description of experience as it unfolds.[164][165][166] His student Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) adopted this method into an approach he termed fundamental ontology. He explored how human pre-understanding of reality shapes human experience of and engagement with the world. He thought that pure description alone is not sufficient for phenomenology. Instead, it should be accompanied by interpretation to discover and avoid possible misunderstandings.[164][167][168] This line of thought was further developed by his student Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900–2002). Gadamer held that human pre-understanding is dynamic and changes in the process of interpretation. He tried to explain this process as a fusion of horizons. The fusion of horizons involves an interplay between the person's current horizon and the horizon of the object of interpretation.[169]
Another influential current of thought in Heidegger's philosophy is his emphasis on how humans care about the world. He explored how this is related to phenomena like anxiety and authenticity. These ideas influenced Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980), who developed the philosophy of existentialism. Existentialists hold that humans are fundamentally free and responsible for their own choices. They also claim that life lacks a predetermined purpose and choosing one's path without such a guiding purpose can lead to anxiety. The statement that the universe is meaningless was especially emphasized by absurdist intellectuals like Albert Camus (1913–1960).[170][171][172]
Critical Theory emerged in the first half of the 20th century in the Frankfurt School of philosophy. It is a form of social philosophy that aims to provide a reflective assessment and critique of society and culture. Unlike traditional theory, its goal is not only to understand and explain but also to bring about change on a practical level, in particular, to emancipate people and liberate them from domination and oppression. Some of its key themes are power, inequality, social justice, and the role of ideology. Notable figures include Theodor Adorno (1903–1969), Max Horkheimer (1895–1973), and Herbert Marcuse (1898–1979).[173][174][175]
The second half of 20th-century continental philosophy was characterized by a critical attitude toward many traditional philosophical concepts and assumptions, such as the concepts of truth, objectivity, universal explanations, reason, and progress. This outlook is sometimes labelled postmodernism. Michel Foucault (1926–1984) examined the relation between knowledge and power. He tried to show how knowledge is always shaped by power. Jacques Derrida (1930–2004) developed the philosophy of deconstruction. Deconstruction aims to expose hidden contradictions within philosophical texts by subverting the oppositions they depend on. Examples are the opposition between presence and absence or between subject and object. Gilles Deleuze (1925–1995) drew on psychoanalytic theory to criticize and reimagine traditional concepts like desire, subjectivity, identity, and knowledge.[176]
Arabic-Persian
Arabic-Persian philosophy covers the philosophical tradition associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of Arabic- and Persian-speaking regions. Other common labels for roughly the same tradition are Islamic philosophy or philosophy in the Islamic world.[177][178]
The classical period of Arabic-Persian philosophy started in the early 9th century CE, roughly 200 years after the death of Prophet Muhammad. It spanned until the late 12th century CE and formed part of the Islamic Golden Age. The early classical period covered the philosophy before Avicenna and had a particular emphasis on translations and interpretations of Ancient Greek philosophy. The late classical period after Avicenna was shaped by the engagement with his comprehensive philosophical system.[179]
Arabic-Persian philosophy proved influential for Western philosophy. During the early medieval period, many of the Greek texts were not available in Western Europe. They became accessible in the later medieval period thanks to the preservation and transmission by the Arabic-Persian intellectual tradition.[180][181][182]
Kalam and early classical
The early Arabic intellectual tradition before the classical period was characterized by various theological discussions. They focused primarily on the question of the correct understanding of the Islamic revelation. Some historians see this already as part of Arabic-Persian philosophy while others draw a more narrow distinction between theology (kalam) and philosophy proper (falsafa). Theologians implicitly accepted the truth of the revelation and restricted their inquiry to the field of religion, such as proofs of the existence of God. The philosophers, on the other hand, investigated a wider range of topics and also explored claims not directly covered by the scriptures. [183]
Early classical Arabic-Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophy. This concerned specifically the philosophy of Aristotle but includes also other philosophers, such as Plato. It happened both through translations and comprehensive commentaries. A key motivation of this process was to integrate and reconcile Greek philosophy with Islamic thought. Islamic philosophers emphasized the role of rational inquiry and examined how to harmonize reason and revelation.[177][184]
Al-Kindi (801–873) is often considered the first philosopher of this tradition in contrast to the more theological works of his predecessors.[185][186] He followed Aristotle in seeing metaphysics as the first philosophy and the highest science. From his theological outlook, it studies the essence and attributes of God. He drew on Plotinus's doctrine of the One to argue for the oneness and perfection of God. For him, God emanates the universe by "bringing being to be from non-being". In the field of psychology, he argued for a dualism that draws a strict distinction for humans concerning their immortal souls in contrast to their mortal bodies. Al-Kindi was a prolific author and published about 270 treatises in his lifetime.[187][188][189]
Al-Farabi (c.872–950) was strongly influenced by Al-Kindi and accepted his emanationist theory of creation. Al-Farabi claimed that philosophy, rather than theology, is the best pathway to truth. His interest in logic earned him the title "the second master" after Aristotle. He came to the conclusion that logic is universal and constitutes the foundation of all language and thought. This contradicts certain passages in the Quran which assign this role to Arabic grammar. In his political philosophy, Al-Farabi accepted Plato's idea that a philosopher-king would be the best ruler. He discussed the virtues such a ruler should have, the tasks they should engage in, and the reasons why this ideal is not realized. Al-Farabi also provided an influential classification of the different sciences and fields of inquiry.[190][191]
Later classical
Avicenna (980–1037) drew on the philosophies of the Ancient Greeks and Al-Farabi to develop a comprehensive philosophical system. It aimed to provide a holistic and rational understanding of reality that encompasses science, religion, and mysticism. He saw logic as the foundation of rational inquiry. In the field of metaphysics, he held that substances can exist by themselves while accidents always depend on something else. For example, color is an accident that requires a body to exist. Avicenna distinguished between two forms of existence: contingent and necessary existence. God has necessary existence. Everything in the world was caused by God and only exists contingently. In the field of psychology, he saw souls as substances that bring things to life. Plants have the lowest form of souls. The souls of animals and humans have additional faculties, like the ones responsible for the power to move, sense, and think rationally. In the field of ethics, Avicenna recommended the pursuit of moral perfection, which can be achieved by following the teachings of the Quran. His system exerted a profound influence on both Islamic and Western philosophy.[192]
Al-Ghazali (1058–1111) was very critical of Avicenna's rational method and his adoption of Greek philosophy. He was skeptical about the capacity of reason to arrive at a true understanding of reality, God, and religion. He saw the philosophy of other Islamic philosophers as an illness. In his book The Incoherence of the Philosophers, he claimed that many philosophical teachings are filled with contradictions and incompatible with Islamic faith. However, he was not outright opposed to philosophy and assigned it a positive but limited place in Islam. He argued that philosophy should be accompanied by a form of mystical intuition to come to a deeper understanding. This intuition relies on direct personal experience and spiritual insight.[193]
Averroes (1126–1198) rejected the skeptical outlook of Al-Ghazali. He tried to show the harmony between the philosophical pursuit of knowledge and the spiritual dimensions of faith. His philosophy relied heavily on Aristotle's teachings. He often criticized Avicenna for departing too much from Aristotle. In the field of psychology, Averroes claimed that there is only one universal intellect shared by all humans. Averroes did not have much influence on subsequent Islamic scholarship but had a more significant impact on European philosophy.[194]
Post-classical
Averroes is often considered the last philosopher of the classical era. The traditional view is that the following post-classical period was marked by a decline on different levels. On the one hand, it is concerned the global influence of Islam. On the other hand, it affected scientific and philosophical inquiry in the Islamic world. Al-Ghazali's doubts about the power of reason and the role of philosophy played an important part in this development. The focus shifted instead to theology and religious doctrine.[195][196][197] However, some contemporary scholars have questioned the magnitude of this decline. According to their view, it is better understood as a shift of philosophical interest than a decline. This means that philosophy did not cease but was absorbed and lived on in theology.[198][199]
Mulla Sadra (1571–1636) is often seen as the most influential philosopher after the classical era. He belonged to the philosophical and mystical school known as illuminationism. He saw philosophy as a spiritual practice to foster wisdom and transform oneself into a sage. In metaphysics, his theory of existence was particularly influential. Mulla rejected the traditional idea, associated with Aristotle, that reality is made up of substances that possess static essences. Instead of this substance metaphysics, he advocated a process philosophy that emphasized continuous change and novelty. According to this view, the creation of the world is not a singular event in the past but an ongoing process. Mulla argued for a synthesis of monism and pluralism by claiming that there is a transcendent unity of being that encompasses all individual entities. He further defended panpsychism by claiming that all entities are conscious but have different degrees of consciousness.[200][201][202]
The movement of Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries in response to the cultural changes associated with modernity and the increasing influence of Western thought. Islamic modernists aimed to understand the role of traditional Islamic doctrines and practices in the emerging modern world. They sought to reinterpret and adapt Islamic teachings to show how the core tenets of Islam are compatible with the principle of modernity in the context of topics like democracy, human rights, science, and colonialism.[203][204][205]
Indian
Indian philosophy is the philosophical tradition that originated on the Indian subcontinent. It can be divided into the ancient period, which lasted until the end of the 2nd century CE, the classical and medieval period, which lasted until the end of the 18th century CE, and the modern period afterward.[206][207] Indian philosophy is characterized by a deep interest in the nature of ultimate reality. It relates this topic to the field of spirituality and asks questions about how to connect with the divine and reach a state of enlightenment. In this regard, Indian philosophers often acted as gurus in their role of guiding spiritual seekers.[208][209]
Indian philosophy is traditionally divided into orthodox and heterodox schools of thought. They are referred to as āstikas and nāstikas. Their exact definition is disputed. The orthodox schools usually accept the authority of the religious scriptures known as the Vedas. They tend to accept the existence of the self (Atman) and ultimate reality (Brahman). There are six orthodox schools: Nyāyá, Vaiśeṣika, Sāṃkhya, Yoga, Mīmāṃsā, and Vedānta. The heterodox schools are defined negatively as those that are not orthodox. The main ones are Buddhism and Jainism.[209][210][211]
Ancient
The ancient period in Indian philosophy started roughly 900 BCE and lasted until 200 CE. In this period, the Vedas were written. They are the religious texts that form the foundation of a lot of Indian philosophy. They cover many topics, including hymns and rituals. Of special interest to philosophy are the Upanishads. They are late Vedic texts that discuss philosophical topics. Some theorists see the Vedas as part of philosophy proper while others treat them as a form of proto-philosophy. This period also saw the emergence of non-Vedic movements, like Buddhism and Jainism.[212][213][209]
The Upanishads introduce key concepts in Indian philosophy, like Atman and Brahman. Atman is the self. It is seen as the eternal soul that constitutes the essence of every conscious being. Brahman is ultimate reality. It is the highest principle governing the universe. The Upanishads explore how Atman and Brahman are related. A key idea is that gaining a proper understanding of their relation is a step on the spiritual path toward liberation. Some Upanishads associate this with an asceticist ideal that involves withdrawing from the world to reach self-realization. Others put more emphasis on an active engagement with the world. This is based on the idea that people have social duties to their families and other people. The laws they prescribe are called dharma and depend both on one's social class and one's stage of life. Another influential idea is that individual souls are caught in a cycle of rebirth. According to this view, a person's actions in their past life affect their next life. This is known as the law of karma.[212][214][215]
The Vedas had a wide influence but not all Indian philosophy originated from them. For example, the non-Vedic movements of Buddhism and Jainism emerged in the 6th century BCE. They agreed with certain Vedic teachings about the cycle of rebirth and the importance of seeking liberation. But they rejected many of the rituals and the social order described in the Vedas. Buddhism was founded by Gautama Siddhartha (563–483 BCE). Gautama challenged the Vedic idea of Atman by arguing that there is no permanent, stable self. He claimed that the belief in a permanent self leads to suffering and that liberation can be attained by realizing the absence of a permanent self.[216][217]
Jainism was founded by Mahavira (599–527 BCE). Jainists practice respect toward all forms of life. This is expressed in their principle of non-violence. It prohibits killing or harming other beings in action or in thought. Another pillar of Jainism is the claim that there are no absolute truths. It is based on the idea that reality is complex and has many different sides to it, which is why it can not always be adequately expressed in language. The last pillar of Jainism is the practice of asceticism or non-attachment. It implies that practitioners do not become emotionally attached to worldy things and do not cling to them.[216][218][219]
Classical and medieval
The classical and medieval period in Indian philosophy started roughly 200 BCE and lasted until 1800 CE. Some theorists use the term "classical period" to refer to this whole duration. Others divide this age into two distinct periods: a classical period until 1300 CE and a medieval period afterward. The orthodox schools, known as the darsanas, developed in the first half of this period. Their foundational scriptures usually take the form of sūtras. Sūtras are aphorisms or short texts that explain key ideas. The second half of this period was characterized by detailed commentaries on the individual sutras. They aimed to provide comprehensive explanations and interpretations.[220][221][222]
Samkhya is the oldest of the darśanas. It is a dualistic philosophy claiming that reality is made of two principles: Purusha, or pure consciousness, and Prakriti, or matter. Samkhya teaches that Prakriti is characterized by three qualities called gunas. Sattva is the guna associated with calmness and harmony. Rajas corresponds to passion and activity. The guna of tamas involves ignorance and inertia.[223][224] The Yoga school formed initially part of Samkhya and only became an independent school later. It is based on the Yoga Sutras of Patanjali and gives special importance to the practice of physical postures and different forms of meditation.[223][225][226]
Nyaya and Vaisheshika are further orthodox schools. In the field of epistemology, Nyaya claims that there are four sources of knowledge: perception, inference, analogical reasoning, and testimony. It is particularly interested in the role of inference and developed an influential theory of logic. According to it, inference depends on a prior perception of an object. It aims to arrive at new information, for example, about the cause of this object. The school of Vaisheshika is known for its atomistic metaphysics. Nyaya and Vaisheshika were originally treated as separate schools but were later seen as a single tradition.[223][227]
The schools of Vedānta and Mīmāṃsā focus on the interpretation of the Vedic scriptures. Vedānta deals primarily with the Upanishads. It discusses metaphysical theories and explores how knowledge and liberation are possible. Mīmāṃsā, on the other hand, is more concerned with the ritualistic practices found in the Vedas.[223][228]
Buddhist philosophy in this period was also vibrant and saw the development of the four main schools of Indian Buddhism. They are Sarvāstivāda, Sautrāntika, Madhyamaka, and Yogācāra. They all agree with the core teachings of Gautama but have certain key differences. The Sarvāstivāda school holds that "all exists", including past, present, and future entities. This position is denied by the Sautrāntika school, which claims that there is nothing outside the present. The Madhyamaka school was founded by Nagarjuna (c. 150–250), who claimed that all phenomena are inherently empty. This means that nothing has a permanent essence or an independent existence. The Yogācāra school is traditionally interpreted as a form of idealism that argues that the external world is an illusion constructed by the mind.[223][229][230]
Both the orthodox and the heterodox schools of Indian philosophy saw various developments in the later half of the classical period. Those developments often happened in the form of detailed commentaries focusing on their foundational sutras. The impact of the Vedanta school significantly grew during this period. It developed different schools, like the school of Advaita Vedanta under the influence of Adi Shankara (c.700–750). Shankara defended a radical monism. He claimed that Atman and Brahman are identical and that the impression of a universe consisting of many distinct entities is an illusion.[231][232]
This idea was slightly modified by Ramanuja (1017–1137)[lower-alpha 2], who developed the school of Vishishtadvaita Vedanta. He agreed that Brahman is the ultimate reality. However, he argued that individual entities, like qualities, persons, and objects, are also real as aspects or parts of the underlying unity of Brahman.[235] He emphasized the role of Bhakti or devotion toward the divine as a spiritual path and helped to popularize the Bhakti movement, which lasted until the 17th to 18th century.[236]
Another important development in this period in the Nyaya school was the emergence of the Navya-Nyāya movement. It provided a more sophisticated framework of logic with a particular focus on linguistic analysis.[232][237]
Modern
The modern period in Indian philosophy started roughly 1800 CE. This period saw many social and cultural changes, specifically as a result of British rule and the introduction of English education. This had various effects on Indian philosophers. Previously, philosophy was done mostly in the language of Sanskrit but now many began to write in English. An example is the influential multi-volume book A History of Indian Philosophy by Surendranath Dasgupta (1887–1952). Philosophers in this period stood under the influence of both their own traditions and new ideas from Western philosophy.[238][239]
Various philosophers in this period tried to provide encompassing systems to unite and harmonize the diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought. For example, Swami Vivekananda (1863–1902) emphasized the validity and universality of all religions. He tried to use the ideas of Advaita Vedanta to show how the different religious traditions are different paths that lead to the same spiritual truth. According to Advaita Vedanta, there is only one ultimate truth without any distinctions or divisions. It sees the diversity and multiplicity in the world as an illusion that hides the underlying divine oneness. According to Vivekananda, different religions are different ways of realizing this divine oneness.[240]
A similar project was pursued by Sri Aurobindo in his integral philosophy. His complex philosophical system aims to show how the different historical and philosophical movements form part of a global evolution of consciousness.[241][242][243] Other contributions to Indian philosophy were made by spiritual teachers like Sri Ramakrishna, Ramana Maharshi, and Jiddu Krishnamurti.[244][245][246]
Chinese
Chinese philosophy covers the philosophical thought associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of China. Various periodizations of this tradition exist. One periodization divides Chinese philosophy into an early period before the Qin dynasty, a period until the emergence of the Song dynasty, a period until the end of the Qing dynasty, and a modern era afterward. The three main schools of Chinese philosophy are Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism. Other influential schools are Mohism and Legalism.[247]
Within traditional Chinese thought, philosophy was not clearly distinguished from religious thought and other types of inquiry.[248] It was primarily concerned with the topics of ethics and society. In comparison to other traditions, it gave less emphasis to metaphysics. Philosophical practice tended to focus on practical wisdom and philosophers often had the role of a sage or a thoughtful advisor.[249][250][208]
Pre-Qin
The first period in Chinese philosophy started in the 6th century BCE and lasted until the rise of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE.[251][250][252] The concept of Dao played a central role in this period. The term is often translated as "the Way" and has different functions in the different schools of thought. Early Chinese philosophy was dominated by the teachings of Confucius (551–479 BCE). For him, a good life is a life that aligns with the Dao. He understood this primarily in terms of moral conduct and acting in accordance with virtues. For example, he argued that people should respect their elders and should practice a form of universal altruism. The family plays a central role in his philosophy. He held that each member of a family has to fulfill their role to ensure that the family as a whole flourishes. He conceptualized the state as a large family and emphasized the importance of harmony in society.[253]
Laozi (6th century BCE) is traditionally seen as the founder of Daoism. Like Confucius, he held that to live a good life is to live in harmony with the Dao. Unlike Confucius, his main focus was not only on society but included the relation between humans and nature. His concept of wu wei was particularly influential. The term is usually translated as "effortless action". It refers to acting in a natural flow that is in accordance with the Dao. Laozi saw this as an ideal state involving spontaneity and ease.[254]
The Daoist philosopher Zhuangzi (399–295 BCE) used parables and allegories to convey his ideas. To clarify the concept of wu wei in everyday life, he gave the example of a butcher. After many years of practice, the butcher arrived at a point where his knife automatically followed the optimal line when cutting an ox without any conscious effort. Zhuangzi is also known for his story of the butterfly dream, which questions the nature of subjective experiences. In this story, he wakes up from a dream in which he was a butterfly. Now he is not sure anymore whether he is a man who dreamt that he was a butterfly or a butterfly dreaming that it is a man.[255][256][257]
The school of Mohism was founded by Mozi (c. 470-391 BCE). Central to Mozi's philosophy is the concept of jian ai, which expresses a form of universal love or impartial caring. Based on this concept, he advocated an early form of consequentialism by arguing that political action should promote the welfare of the people.[255][258][259]
Qin to pre-Song dynasties
The following period started with the establishment of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE and lasted until the rise of the Song dynasty in 960 CE. This period stood under the influence of Xuanxue philosophy, legalist philosophy, and the spread of Buddhism. Xuanxue, also known as neo-Daoism, tried to synthesize Confucianism and Daoism. At the same time, it developed a metaphysical framework for these schools of thought. It assumed that the Dao is the root of ultimate reality. It questioned whether this root should be understood as being or non-being. According to the philosophers He Yan (c.195–249 CE) and Wang Bi (226–249 CE), it is a formless non-being that acts as the source of all things and phenomena. This view was rejected by Pei Wei (267–300 CE), who argued that non-being is unable to give rise to being. Instead, he held that being gives rise to itself.[260]
In the field of ethics and politics, the school of legalism became particularly influential. It rejected the Mohist idea that politics aims at the promotion of general welfare. Instead, legalists argued that statecraft is about wielding power and establishing order. They also rejected the Confucianist emphasis on the role of virtues and moral conduct to have a harmonious society. By contrast, they argued that the best way to achieve order is to establish laws and punish people who transgress them.[255][261][262]
Buddhism arrived in India in the 1st century CE. In the early phase, Buddhist philosophers were primarily concerned with the translation of the original Sanskrit texts into Chinese. But later, new and distinctive forms of Chinese Buddhism developed. For example, Tiantai Buddhism was founded in the 6th century CE. Its doctrine of the Threefold Truth tries to reconcile two opposed positions. The first truth of conventional realism affirms the existence of regular things. The second truth is a more skeptical position holding that all phenomena are illusory or empty. The third truth aims to reconcile these two positions by claiming that the mundane world is both real and empty at the same time. This period also saw the rise of Chan Buddhism, which later prompted the development of Zen Buddhism in Japan. In the field of epistemology, Chan Buddhists hold that there is a form of immediate acquaintance with things. They claim that it avoids the distortions of linguistic distinctions and results in direct knowledge of ultimate reality.[263][264]
Song to Qing dynasties and modern
The next period started with the emergence of the Song dynasty in 960 CE. Some scholars take it to end with the opium wars in 1840 while others extend it all the way to the emergence of the Republic of China in 1912. In this period, neo-Confucianism was particularly influential. In contrast to earlier forms of Confucianism, it placed more emphasis on metaphysics. This came about as a reaction to similar developments in Daoism and Buddhism. It rejected their emphasis on non-being and emptiness. It focused on the concept of li instead as a positive foundation of metaphysics. Li is understood as the rational principle that is the ground of being and governs all entities. It also underlies human nature and is the source of virtues. Li is sometimes contrasted with qi as a material and vital force.[265][250]
The later part of the Qing dynasty and the following modern period were characterized by the encounter with Western philosophy. This included various philosophers, like Plato, Kant, and Mill as well as movements like pragmatism. But of special importance were Marx's ideas of class struggle, socialism, and communism. His critique of capitalism and his ideal of a classless society led to the development of Chinese Marxism. In this regard, Mao Zedong (1893–1976) acted both as a philosopher expounding these ideas as well as a revolutionary leader committed to their practical implementation. Chinese Marxism differed in various respects from classical Marxism. For example, in classical Marxism, the proletariat is responsible both for the rise of the capitalist economy and for the subsequent socialist revolution. In Mao's Marxism, on the other hand, this role falls to the peasantry guided by the Communist Party.[266]
The influence of traditional Chinese thought also remained strong in the modern period. This is reflected, for example, in the philosophy of Liang Shuming (1893-1988). Liang was influenced by Confucianism, Buddhism, and Western philosophy. He is often seen as the founder of the school of thought known as new Confucianism. He advocated a balanced life attitude characterized by a harmony between humanity and nature as a way to true happiness. He criticized the modern European attitude for being overly concerned with exploiting nature for satisfying desires. He saw the Indian attitude with its focus on the divine and abstaining from desires as a mistake in the other direction.[267]
Others
Ninian Smart wrote that there are various traditions which developed their own distinctive philosophical ideas. In some cases, these developments happened independently while in others, they were influenced by the main traditions.[268]
Japanese
Japanese philosophy is characterized by its engagement with various traditions, including Chinese, Indian, and Western schools of thought. Ancient philosophy was shaped by Shinto, its indigenous religion. It included a form of animism that saw natural phenomena and objects as spirits, the so-called kami. The arrival of Confucianism and Buddhism in the 5th and 6th centuries CE transformed the intellectual landscape and led to various subsequent developments. Confucianism influenced political and social philosophy and was further developed in different strands of neo-Confucianism. Japanese Buddhist thought developed particularly in the traditions of Pure Land Buddhism and Zen Buddhism. In the 19th and 20th centuries, the interaction with Western thinkers was a major influence on Japanese philosophy. This concerned in particular the schools of existentialism and phenomenology. This period saw the foundation of the Kyoto School. It was founded by Kitaro Nishida (1870–1945). He criticized Western philosophy associated with Kantianism for relying on the distinction between subject and object. He tried to overcome this problem by developing the concept of basho. Basho—usually translated as "place"—may be understood as an experiential domain that transcends the dichotomy between subject and object. Other influential members of the Kyoto school were Tanabe Hajime (1885–1962) and Nishitani Keiji (1900–1990).[269]
Latin American
Philosophy in Latin America is often included in Western philosophy. However, in a more narrow sense, it is a distinct tradition that features its own characteristics despite the strong Western influence. Philosophical ideas concerning the nature of reality and the role of humans in it are found in its indigenous civilizations, like the Aztecs, the Maya, and the Inca. This theorizing happened independently of European influence. But most discussions usually focus on the colonial and post-colonial periods since very few texts of the pre-colonial period survived. The colonial period was dominated by a focus on religious philosophy in the form of scholasticism. In the 18th and 19th centuries, the emphasis shifted to enlightenment philosophy and the adoption of a scientific outlook in the form of positivism. An influential current in the later part of the 20th century was the philosophy of liberation. It was inspired by Marxism and focused on topics like political liberation, intellectual independence, and education.[270]
African
In the widest sense, African philosophy covers philosophical ideas that originated anywhere in the African continent. However, the term is often understood in a more narrow sense to relate primarily to the regions of western and sub-Saharan Africa.[271] The philosophical tradition in Africa derived from both ancient Egypt and scholarly texts in medieval Africa.[272] While early African intellectual history was focused on folklore, wise sayings, and religious ideas, it also included some philosophical ideas, such as the concept of Ubuntu. It is usually translated as humanity or humanness. Ubuntu philosophy emphasized that people are connected to each other on a moral level and should practice kindness and compassion.[273] During the 17th century, Ethiopian philosophy developed a literary tradition as exemplified by Zera Yacob.[274][275] The emergence of systematic African philosophy is often traced to the beginning of the 20th century. An important movement in this period was excavationism. It aimed to reconstruct traditional African worldviews, often with the goal of rediscovering a lost African identity. However, this approach was rejected by so-called Afro-deconstructionists, who denied the existence of a unique African identity. Other influential strands and topics in modern African thought are ethnophilosophy, négritude, pan-Africanism, Marxism, postcolonialism, and the critique of Eurocentrism.[276]
References
Notes
Citations
- Santinello & Piaia 2010, pp. 487–488.
- Copleston 2003, pp. 4–6.
- Verene 2008, pp. 6–8.
-
- Scharfstein 1998, pp. 1–4
- Perrett 2016, Is there Indian philosophy?
- Smart 2008, pp. 1–3
- Rescher 2014, p. 173
- Parkinson 2005, p. 1–2
-
- Laerke, Smith & Schliesser 2013, pp. 115–118
- Verene 2008, p. 6–8
- Frede 2022, p. x
- Beaney 2013, p. 60
- Chimisso 2016, p. 70
- Gracia 2006.
- Lamprecht 1939, pp. 449–451.
- Frede 2022, p. ix–x.
-
- Frede 2022, pp. x–xiii, 79
- Santinello & Piaia 2010, pp. 487–488
- Copleston 2003, p. 4–10
- Park 2013, p. 130
- Heller 2016, pp. 154–156.
- Taylor 1997, p. ii.
- Grayling 2019, preface.
- Smart 2008, pp. 1–2.
- Iannone 2013, p. 12.
- Heidegger 2015, p. 30.
- Fletcher et al. 2020, pp. 8–15.
- Blackson 2011, Introduction.
- Sisko 2018, Introduction to volume 1.
- Graham 2023, 1. Presocratic Thought.
- Duignan 2010, pp. 9–11.
- Rée & Urmson 2004, p. 309.
- Dobson 2016, pp. 106–108.
- Graham 2023, 1d. Heraclitus.
- Dobson 2016, pp. 112–115.
- Graham 2023, 1e. Parmenides and Zeno.
- Graham 2023, 1g. Democritus and Atomism.
- Lawson 2004, p. 63.
- Graham 2023, 2. Socrates.
- Singer 2023, Socrates.
- Taylor 1997, pp. 298–316.
- Graham 2023, 3. Plato.
- Taylor 1997, pp. 329–354.
- Fine 2019, p. 540.
- Hughes & Gosney 2016, p. 43.
- Murphy 2015, p. 4.
-
- Graham 2023, 4. Aristotle
- Furley 2005, pp. 1–5, 40–69
- Grayling 2019, Aristotle
- Haaparanta 2009, p. 3–4
- Buren 2023, p. 1
- Long 1986, p. 1.
- Blackson 2011, Chapter 10.
- Graham 2023, 5. Hellenistic Thought.
- Furley 2005, pp. 188–221.
- Grayling 2019, Epicureanism.
-
- Graham 2023, 5. Hellenistic Thought
- Furley 2005, pp. 222–252
- Grayling 2019, Stoicism
- Green & Brink 2003, p. lxxxviii
-
- Graham 2023, 5. Hellenistic Thought
- Vogt 2022, lead section, 1. The Central Questions
- Furley 2005, pp. 253–286
- Grayling 2019, Scepticism
-
- Graham 2023, 6. Post-Hellenistic Thought
- Adamson 2015, pp. 209–215
- Furley 2005, pp. 357–388
- Camus 2007, p. 45
- Lawson 2004, p. 200
-
- Duignan 2010a, p. 9
- Lagerlund 2020, p. v
- Marenbon 2023, lead section
- MacDonald & Kretzmann 1996, lead section
- Grayling 2019, Part II: Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy.
- Adamson 2019, pp. 3–4.
-
- MacDonald & Kretzmann 1996, lead section
- Russell 2005, p. 380
- Kaye 2012, p. 47
- Adamson 2019, pp. 290–296
- Grayling 2019, Augustine.
- O'Meara 1981, pp. 39–40.
- Warren 2008, pp. 94–95.
-
- Adamson 2019, p. 11
- Grayling 2019, Boethius
- Dehsen 2013, p. 31
- Kaylor & Phillips 2012, pp. 179–181
- Frassetto 2013, p. 121
- Sweeney 2016, p. 10–11
- Grayling 2019, Abelard.
- Penner.
- Barmann 1972, p. 18.
- Marias 2012, p. 153.
- Dougherty 2009, p. 120.
- Pasnau & Dyke 2014, Chapter 19.
- Grayling 2019, Anselm.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 10.
- Crowder 2016, p. 34.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 4.
- Grayling 2019, Aquinas.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 185.
- Kerr.
- Murphy 2019, 1. Key Features of Natural Law Theories.
- Mackey & Elvey 2020, p. 17.
- Adamson 2019, pp. 252–4.
- Elders 1990, pp. 83–85.
- Grayling 2019, Duns Scotus.
- Marenbon 2004, pp. 297–298.
- Cross 1999, p. 149.
- Grayling 2019, Ockham.
- Spade & Panaccio 2019, lead section, 4.1 Ockham’s Razor.
-
- Parkinson 2005, pp. 1–14
- Adamson 2022, pp. 155–157
- Grayling 2019, Philosophy in the Renaissance
- Chambre et al. 2023, Renaissance philosophy
- Grayling 2019, Renaissance Platonism.
- Robb 2021, Introduction.
- Komar 2003, p. 79.
- Adamson 2022, pp. 155–157.
-
- Grendler 2010
- Baker 2015, Introduction
- Chambre et al. 2023, Renaissance philosophy
- Parkinson 2005, pp. 1–14
- Chambre et al. 2023, Renaissance philosophy.
- Adamson 2022, pp. 298–304.
- Grayling 2019, Renaissance Political Thought.
- Parkinson 2005, pp. 1–14.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 20.
- Ge (葛云保) 2022, pp. 157–159.
- Adamson 2022, pp. 387–394.
-
- Grayling 2019, The Rise of Modern Thought; The Eighteenth-century Enlightenment
- Anstey & Vanzo 2023, pp. 236–237
- Dobre & Nyden 2013, p. 4
- Ongaro 2020, p. 64
-
- Dehsen 2013, p. 115
- Leahey 2017, p. 158
- Stevenson 2014, p. 145–146
- Chappell 1994, p. 60
- Dehsen 2013, p. 26.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 76–79.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 91.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 80–85.
- Kurki 2008, pp. 33–40.
- Grayling 2019, The Rise of Modern Thought.
- Vesey 1976, pp. 154–158.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 33–40.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 51.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 61–69.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 179.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 70–75.
- Grayling 2019, Leibniz.
- Grayling 2019, The Eighteenth-Century Enlightenment.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 90–92.
- Grayling 2019, Kant.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 105.
- Tucker 2017, p. 269.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 88.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 41–46.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 163.
- Kenny 2006, pp. 93–96.
- Grayling 2019, Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century.
- Fletcher et al. 2020, pp. 14–15.
- Ten 2005, pp. 1–3.
- Smart 2008, pp. 290–297.
- Beiser 1987, pp. 8–15, 123–125.
- di Giovanni 2005.
-
- Santis, Hopkins & Majolino 2020, p. 93
- Kenny 2006, pp. 108–111
- Whistler 2013, p. 73
- Critchley 2001, p. 31
- Tritten & Whistler 2018, p. 150
- Kenny 2006, pp. 111–116.
- Critchley 2001, p. 31.
- Grayling 2019, Hegel.
- Houlgate 2005, pp. 1–3, 181.
- Illetterati & Miolli 2021, pp. 25–26.
- Colapietro 2003, pp. 42–43.
- Grayling 2019, Idealism.
- Kenny 2007, pp. 47–50.
- Kenny 2007, pp. 18–24.
- Dehsen 2013, p. 127.
-
- Kenny 2007, pp. 13–16
- Dehsen 2013, p. 171
- Janaway 1989, p. 258–259
- Critchley 2001, p. 31
-
- Kenny 2007, pp. 30–33
- Dehsen 2013, p. 144
- Ramgotra & Choat 2023, p. 244
- Critchley 2001, p. 31
- Dehsen 2013, pp. 25, 132.
- Ten 2005, pp. 4–25.
- Dehsen 2013, pp. 96, 152.
- Grayling 2019, Pragmatism.
- Gavin 2012, p. 1.
- Brinkmann 2018, pp. 102–103.
- Grayling 2019, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, Analytic Philosophy, Continental Philosophy.
- Marino & Terzi 2020, pp. 24–25.
- Grayling 2019, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century.
- Waithe 1995, pp. xix–xxiii.
-
- Atkin 2010
- Gavin 2012, p. 1
- Brinkmann 2018, p. 102–103
- Grayling 2019, Pragmatism
- Legg & Hookway 2008, lead section
- Grayling 2019, Feminism.
- Fletcher et al. 2020, p. 15.
- Hurka 2021, 2. Metaethical Innovations, 3. Impersonal Consequentialism, 4. The Ideal.
- Grayling 2019, Moore.
- Canfield 2005, pp. 89–94.
- O'Regan 2016, p. 231.
- Shanker 2004, pp. 124–149.
- Kenny 2007, pp. 50–54.
- Pérez-Jara & Camprubí 2022, p. 32.
- Kenny 2007, pp. 54–58, 60–63.
- Shanker 2004, pp. 157–192.
- Shanker 2004, pp. 193–213.
- Fennell 2019, p. 173.
- Lovat et al. 2011, p. 29.
- Grayling 2019, Quine.
- Decock 2002, pp. 231–250.
- Grayling 2019, Ordinary Language Philosophy.
- Parker-Ryan 2023, lead section.
- Grayling 2019, Ethics, Political Philosophy.
- Duignan 2011, pp. 114–118.
- Boundas 2007, pp. 299–302.
- Chambre et al. 2023, The phenomenology of Husserl and Heidegger.
- Nyiro 2019, p. 165.
- Lévinas 1995, p. 147.
- Wheeler 2020, 2.2.1 The Question.
- Crotty 1998, p. 97.
- Chambre et al. 2023, The existentialism of Jaspers and Sartre.
- Grayling 2019, Sartre.
- Gordon 1984, p. 15.
- Bohman, Flynn & Celikates 2021, lead section.
- Corradetti, lead section.
- Raymond 1996, Critical theory.
-
- Chambre et al. 2023, Recent trends
- Grayling 2019, Deleuze, Derrida
- Dehsen 2013, pp. 48, 68
- Eberle 1994, p. 152
- Nord 2010, p. 107
- Grayling 2019, Arabic-Persian Philosophy.
- Adamson 2016, p. 5.
-
- Adamson & Taylor 2004, p. 1
- EB staff 2020
- Grayling 2019, Arabic-Persian Philosophy
- Reisman 2003, pp. ix–x
- Adamson 2016, p. 5–6
- Ayduz & Dagli 2014, p. 356.
- Hasse 2021, lead section, 1. Transmission.
- Adamson 2016, pp. 161, 295, 421.
-
- Adamson & Taylor 2004, p. 1
- Adamson 2023, p. 54–55
- Adamson 2016, p. 8–9
- Jackson 2014, p. 5
- Inglis 2005, p. 19
- Armstrong 1967, pp. 648–649.
- Nasr & Leaman 2013, 11. Al-Kindi.
- Nasr 2006, pp. 109–110.
- Grayling 2019, Al-Kindi.
- Adamson 2020, lead section, 3. Metaphysics, 4. Psychology.
- Iqbal 2009, p. 43.
- Grayling 2019, Al-Farabi.
- Druart 2021, lead section, 3. Logic, 7. Ethics and Politics.
-
- Gutas 2016
- Grayling 2019, Ibn Sina (Avicenna)
- Baldassarri & Blank 2021, p. 82
- Belo 2007, p. 35
-
- Adamson 2016, pp. 140–146
- Marenbon 2012, pp. 114–115
- Dehsen 2013, p. 75
- Griffel 2020, lead section, 3. Al-Ghazâlî’s “Refutations” of falsafa and Ismâ’îlism, 4. The Place of Falsafa in Islam
-
- Dehsen 2013, p. 18
- Adamson 2016, p. 179–193
- Ben Ahmed & Pasnau 2021
- Kenny 2005, pp. 48–50
- López-Farjeat 2021, p. 9.
- Booth 2017, pp. 143–169, The Philosophers Strike Back: Averroes and Islamic Philosophy After al-Ghazali.
- Grayling 2019, Ibn Rushd (Averroes).
- Griffel 2021, pp. 1–20, 565–566.
- Adamson 2016, pp. 295–302.
- Rizvi 2021, lead section, 3. Metaphysics, 4. Noetics — Epistemology and Psychology.
- Chamankhah 2019, p. 73.
- Moris 2013, pp. 154–155.
- Moaddel 2005, pp. 1–2.
- Masud 2009, pp. 237–238.
- Safi 2005, lead section, §Westernization and Islamic Paradigms.
- Gupta 2012, p. 8.
- Perrett 2016, Indian philosophy: a brief historical overview.
- Smart 2008, p. 3.
- Grayling 2019, Indian Philosophy.
- Smart 2008, pp. 13–15, 27–28.
- Rambachan 2012, pp. 1–2.
- Perrett 2016, Indian philosophy: a brief historical overview, The ancient period of Indian philosophy.
- Pooley & Rothenbuhler 2016, p. 1468.
- Tebbit 2013, p. 400.
- Andrea & Overfield 2015, p. 71.
- Perrett 2016, The ancient period of Indian philosophy.
- Ruether 2004, p. 57.
- Juergensmeyer & Roof 2012, pp. 609–610.
- Hindson & Caner 2008, p. 289.
- Perrett 2016, Indian philosophy: a brief historical overview, The classical period of Indian philosophy, The medieval period of Indian philosophy.
- Glenney & Silva 2019, p. 77.
- Adamson & Ganeri 2020, pp. 101–109.
- Perrett 2016, The classical period of Indian philosophy.
- Ruzsa 2023.
- Vanamali 2015, p. 50.
- Gannon 2020, p. 34.
- Dasti, lead section, 1b. Inference.
- Daniélou 1993, pp. 165–166.
- Fang 2018, p. 23.
- Wolfson 2014, p. 294.
- Dalal 2021, lead section, 1. Life and Works.
- Perrett 2016, The medieval period of Indian philosophy.
- Ranganathan, 1. Rāmānuja’s Life and Works.
- Sydnor 2012, p. 20.
- Ranganathan, lead section, 2c. Substantive Theses.
-
- Ranganathan, 4. Rāmānuja's Soteriology
- Kulke & Rothermund 1998, p. 139
- Seshadri 1996, pp. 297
- Jha 2022, p. 217
- Maharaj 2020, p. 122.
- Perrett 2016, Indian philosophy: a brief historical overview, The modern period of Indian philosophy.
- EB staff 2023.
-
- Banhatti 1995, p. 151–154
- Bilimoria 2018, pp. 529–531
- Rambachan 1994, p. 91–92
- Menon, lead section
- Bilimoria 2018, pp. 529–531.
- Baird 2017, pp. 244–245.
- Prince 2017, p. 133.
- Raghuramaraju 2016, p. 41.
- Paranjape 2016, p. 320.
- Bilimoria 2018, p. 240.
-
- Smart 2008, pp. 70–71
- EB staff 2017
- Littlejohn 2023
- Grayling 2019, Chinese Philosophy
- Zhang 2021, p. 751
- Mou 2009, pp. 1–3.
- Mou 2009, pp. 43–45.
- EB staff 2017.
- Smart 2008, pp. 70–71.
- Littlejohn 2023.
-
- EB staff 2017
- Smart 2008, pp. 71–76
- Littlejohn 2023, 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects
- Boyd & Timpe 2021, p. 64–66
- Liu 2017, p. 209
- Marshev 2021, p. 100–101
-
- EB staff 2017
- Slingerland 2007, pp. 77–78
- Grayling 2019, Chinese Philosophy
- Grayling 2019, Chinese Philosophy.
- Montero 2016, p. 22.
- Chai 2020, pp. 42–43.
- Littlejohn 2023, 1c. Mozi (c. 470-391 B.C.E.) and Mohism.
- Defoort & Standaert 2013, p. 35.
-
- Smart 2008, pp. 70–71
- EB staff 2017
- Littlejohn 2023, 2. Philosophy from the Qin (221 B.C.E.) to the Tang (618 C.E.)
- Wang, Bao & Guan 2020, p. 6–8
- Kim 2019, p. 161.
- Littlejohn 2023, 2a. Syncretic Philosophies in the Qin and Han Periods.
- Littlejohn 2023, Early Buddhism in China.
- Poceski 2014, pp. 165–166.
- Smart 2008, pp. 70–71, 99–102.
-
- Littlejohn 2023, 5. The Chinese and Western Encounter in Philosophy
- Mou 2009, pp. 473–480, 512–513
- Qi 2014, p. 99–100
- Yu 2023, lead section, 5. The Traditional Trend in Modern Chinese Philosophy
-
- Littlejohn 2023, 5. The Chinese and Western Encounter in Philosophy
- Yu 2023, lead section, 5. The Traditional Trend in Modern Chinese Philosophy
- Meynard & Major 2023, pp. 1–16
- Smart 2008, pp. 1–12.
-
- Smart 2008, pp. 126–127, 422–432
- Maraldo 2019, lead section, 3. Theory of Universals and the Logic of Place
- Kasulis 2016a, Logic in Japan
- Kurtz 2012, p. 97–98
- Kasulis 2022, lead section, 3. Five Fountainheads of Japanese Philosophy, 4. Historical Periods of Philosophical Development and Interaction
- Kasulis 2013
- Kasulis 2016, Japanese philosophy
-
- Gracia & Vargas 2018, lead section, 1. History, 2. The Contemporary Period
- Stehn 2023
- Gracia & Millán-Zaibert 2006, Latin American Philosophy
- Iannone 2013, p. 12
-
- Grayling 2019, African Philosophy
- Smart 2008, pp. 433–452
- Chimakonam 2023, lead section, 6. Epochs in African Philosophy
- Janz 2009, p. 74
- Imbo 1998, p. 41.
-
- Grayling 2019, African Philosophy
- Smart 2008, pp. 433–452
- Chimakonam 2023, lead section, 6. Epochs in African Philosophy
- Janz 2009, p. 74
- Wiredu 2008, p. 172.
- Coetzee & Roux 2004, p. 423.
-
- Chimakonam 2014, pp. 4, 34
- Chimakonam 2023, lead section, 1. Introduction, 5. The Movements in African Philosophy, 6. Epochs in African Philosophy
- Bell & Fernback 2015, p. 44
- Coetzee & Roux 1998, pp. 38, 48, 88
- McEwan 2008, pp. 39–40
Sources
- Adamson, Peter; Taylor, Richard C. (9 December 2004). The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-49469-5. Archived from the original on 7 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Adamson, Peter (2020). "al-Kindi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, 3. Metaphysics, 4. Psychology. Archived from the original on 21 May 2019. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Adamson, Peter (10 February 2022). Byzantine and Renaissance Philosophy: A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Volume 6. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 6. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-266992-6. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Adamson, Peter; Ganeri, Jonardon (2020). Classical Indian Philosophy: A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Volume 5. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-885176-9. Archived from the original on 2023-06-29. Retrieved 2023-06-29.
- Adamson, Peter (September 2019). Medieval Philosophy. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 4. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884240-8. Archived from the original on 2023-05-25. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
- Adamson, Peter (2015). Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 2. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3. Archived from the original on 2023-07-11. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
- Adamson, Peter (2016). Philosophy in the Islamic World. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 3. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957749-1. Archived from the original on 2023-05-25. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
- Adamson, Peter (21 April 2023). Studies on Early Arabic Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-94696-3. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Andrea, Alfred J.; Overfield, James H. (1 January 2015). The Human Record: Sources of Global History, Volume I: To 1500. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-1-305-53746-0. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- Anstey, Peter R.; Vanzo, Alberto (31 January 2023). Experimental Philosophy and the Origins of Empiricism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-009-03467-8. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
- Armstrong, A. H. (April 1967). The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521040549. Archived from the original on 2023-05-21. Retrieved 2023-06-16.
- Atkin, Albert (2010). "Pragmatism". Oxford Bibliographies Online. OUP. Archived from the original on 7 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Ayduz, Salim; Dagli, Caner (2014). The Oxford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Science, and Technology in Islam. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-981257-8.
- Baird, Forrest (3 October 2017). Philosophic Classics: Asian Philosophy, Volume VI. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-21744-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Baker, Patrick (29 September 2015). Italian Renaissance Humanism in the Mirror. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-11186-8. Archived from the original on 31 May 2023. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
- Baldassarri, Fabrizio; Blank, Andreas (25 May 2021). Vegetative Powers: The Roots of Life in Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern Natural Philosophy. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-69709-9. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
- Banhatti, G. S. (1995). Life and Philosophy of Swami Vivekananda. Atlantic Publishers & Dist. ISBN 978-81-7156-291-6.
- Barmann, Lawrence F. (27 April 1972). Baron Friedrich Von Hügel and the Modernist Crisis in England. CUP Archive. ISBN 978-0-521-08178-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Beaney, Michael (20 June 2013). The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-166266-9. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Beiser, Frederick C. (1987). The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674020696. Archived from the original on 2023-05-20. Retrieved 2023-06-25.
- Beiser, Frederick (25 August 2011). "Review of Nineteenth Century Philosophy: Revolutionary Responses to the Existing Order". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. University of Notre Dame. Archived from the original on 18 June 2023. Retrieved 18 June 2023.
- Bell, Richard H.; Fernback, Jan (2015). Understanding African Philosophy: A Cross-cultural Approach to Classical and Contemporary Issues. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-94866-5. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-15.
- Belo, Catarina Carriço Marques de Moura (2007). Chance and Determinism in Avicenna and Averroës. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-15587-9. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-19.
- Ben Ahmed, Fouad; Pasnau, Robert (2021). "Ibn Rushd [Averroes]". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Bilimoria, Puruṣottama (2018). History of Indian philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-30976-9.
- Blackson, Thomas A. (6 January 2011). Ancient Greek Philosophy: From the Presocratics to the Hellenistic Philosophers. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4443-9608-9. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Bohman, James; Flynn, Jeffrey; Celikates, Robin (2021). "Critical Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2023.
- Booth, Anthony Robert (2017). "The Philosophers Strike Back: Averroes and Islamic Philosophy After al-Ghazali". Analytic Islamic Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan UK. doi:10.1057/978-1-137-54157-4_7. ISBN 978-1-137-54157-4. Archived from the original on 2023-06-09. Retrieved 2023-06-09.
- Boundas, Constantin V. (2007). Columbia Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-14203-8. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-06.
- Boyd, Craig A.; Timpe, Kevin (25 March 2021). The Virtues: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-258407-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Brinkmann, Svend (2018). Philosophies of Qualitative Research. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-024724-9. Archived from the original on 2023-06-04. Retrieved 2023-06-04.
- Buren, Franziska van (20 March 2023). Aristotle and the Ontology of St. Bonaventure. Leuven University Press. ISBN 978-94-6270-356-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Camus, Albert (2007). Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism. University of Missouri Press. ISBN 978-0-8262-6622-4. Archived from the original on 2023-05-28. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
- Canfield, John V., ed. (2005). Philosophy of Meaning, Knowledge and Value in the Twentieth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-03068-4.
- Chai, David (9 January 2020). Daoist Encounters with Phenomenology: Thinking Interculturally about Human Existence. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-06956-5. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
- Chamankhah, Leila (3 September 2019). The Conceptualization of Guardianship in Iranian Intellectual History (1800–1989): Reading Ibn ʿArabī's Theory of Wilāya in the Shīʿa World. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-22692-3. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Chambre, Henri; Maurer, Armand; Stroll, Avrum; McLellan, David T.; Levi, Albert William; Wolin, Richard; Fritz, Kurt von (2023). "Western philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 13 May 2021. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Chappell, Vere (24 June 1994). The Cambridge Companion to Locke. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-38772-9. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 1 June 2023.
- Chimakonam, Jonathan O. (15 December 2014). Atuolu Omalu: Some Unanswered Questions in Contemporary African Philosophy. University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-7618-6455-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
- Chimakonam, Jonathan O. (2023). "History of African Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 5 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Chimisso, Cristina (11 February 2016). Writing the History of the Mind: Philosophy and Science in France, 1900 to 1960s. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-78815-6. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Coetzee, Pieter Hendrik; Roux, A. P. J. (1998). The African Philosophy Reader. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-18905-7.
- Coetzee, P. H.; Roux, A. P. J. (March 2004). The African Philosophy Reader. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-88419-2.
- Colapietro, Vincent Michael (2003). Fateful Shapes of Human Freedom: John William Miller and the Crises of Modernity. Vanderbilt University Press. ISBN 978-0-8265-1433-2. Archived from the original on 2023-07-11. Retrieved 2023-06-26.
- Copleston, Frederick (1 June 2003). History of Philosophy Volume 1: Greece and Rome. Continuum. ISBN 978-0-8264-6895-6. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Corradetti, Claudio. "Frankfurt School and Critical Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2023.
- Critchley, Simon (22 February 2001). Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-157832-8. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Cross, Richard (17 June 1999). Duns Scotus. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-535225-2. Archived from the original on 30 May 2023. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Crotty, Michael (26 August 1998). The Foundations of Social Research: Meaning and Perspective in the Research Process. SAGE. ISBN 978-1-4462-8313-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Crowder, Jason D. (2 March 2016). Philosophy, Who Needs It?: A Layman's Introduction to Philosophy. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4982-1979-2. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 January 2022. Retrieved 19 June 2023.
- Daniélou, Alain (August 1993). Virtue, Success, Pleasure, and Liberation: The Four Aims of Life in the Tradition of Ancient India. Inner Traditions / Bear & Co. ISBN 978-0-89281-218-9.
- Dasti, Matthew R. "Nyaya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. lead section, 1b. Inference. Archived from the original on 4 October 2012. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- Decock, Lieven (2002). "Quine's Weak and Strong Indispensability Argument". Journal for General Philosophy of Science. 33 (2). doi:10.1023/A:1022471707916. S2CID 117002868.
- Defoort, Carine; Standaert, Nicolas (2013). The Mozi as an Evolving Text: Different Voices in Early Chinese Thought. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-23434-5. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-21.
- Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- di Giovanni, George (2005). Freedom and Religion in Kant and his Immediate Successors: The Vocation of Humankind, 1784–1800. Cambridge University Press.
- Dobre, Mihnea; Nyden, Tammy (29 November 2013). Cartesian Empiricisms. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-7690-6. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
- Dobson, Geoffrey (16 June 2016). A Chaos of Delight: Science, Religion and Myth and the Shaping of Western Thought. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-47872-2.
- Dougherty, Jude P. (2009). Wretched Aristotle: Using the Past to Rescue the Future. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-4006-2. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-05-30.
- Druart, Therese-Anne (2021). "al-Farabi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Duignan, Brian, ed. (15 August 2010). Ancient Philosophy: From 600 BCE to 500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-141-6. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Duignan, Brian, ed. (15 August 2010a). Medieval Philosophy: From 500 to 1500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-143-0. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Duignan, Brian (15 January 2011). The History of Western Ethics. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-301-4. Archived from the original on 6 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Dyrness, William A.; Kärkkäinen, Veli-Matti (25 October 2009). Global Dictionary of Theology: A Resource for the Worldwide Church. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-7811-6. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- EB staff (2017). "Chinese philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2 May 2015. Retrieved 12 June 2023.
- EB staff (2023). "History and periods of Indian philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 11 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- EB staff (2020). "Islamic philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2023-06-07. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
- Eberle, Gary (1994). The Geography of Nowhere: Finding One's Self in the Postmodern World. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-55612-716-8. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
- Elders, Leo (1 January 1990). The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Brill Archive. ISBN 978-90-04-09156-6. Archived from the original on 30 May 2023. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Fang, Litian (21 November 2018). Chinese Buddhism and Traditional Culture. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-51909-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Fennell, John (18 February 2019). A Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Language: Central Themes from Locke to Wittgenstein. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-64906-6. Archived from the original on 6 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Fine, Gail (2019). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-063973-0. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-17.
- Fletcher, Robert; Romero, Paola; Talbot, Marianne; Warburton, Nigel; Whiston, Amna (5 November 2020). Philosophy: A Visual Encyclopedia. Dorling Kindersley Limited. ISBN 978-0-241-50422-2. Archived from the original on 6 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Frassetto, Michael (14 March 2013). The Early Medieval World: From the Fall of Rome to the Time of Charlemagne [2 Volumes]. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-59884-996-7. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Frede, Michael (2022). The Historiography of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884072-5. Archived from the original on 2023-05-24. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
- Furley, David, ed. (2005). II. From Aristotle to Augustine. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02845-2.
- Gannon, Sharon (26 May 2020). Yoga & Veganism: The Diet of Enlightenment. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-64722-185-0. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Gavin, W. J. (6 December 2012). Context Over Foundation: Dewey and Marx. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-009-2903-6. Archived from the original on 4 June 2023. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
- Ge (葛云保), Yunbao (25 January 2022). From Geocentric to Heliocentric: How Discoveries Are Made. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-16-7779-3. Archived from the original on 31 May 2023. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
- Glenney, Brian; Silva, José Filipe (21 February 2019). The Senses and the History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-73106-5. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Gordon, Jeffrey (September 1984). "Nagel or Camus on the Absurd?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 45 (1). doi:10.2307/2107324. JSTOR 2107324.
- Gracia, Jorge; Vargas, Manuel (2018). "Latin American Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 11 June 2018. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Gracia, Jorge J. E. (2006). "History And Historiography Of Philosophy". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on 2021-01-12. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
- Gracia, Jorge J. E.; Millán-Zaibert, Elizabeth (2006). "Latin American Philosophy". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on 2021-01-12. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
- Graham, Jacob N. (2023). "Ancient Greek Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 25 August 2022. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Grayling, A. C. (20 June 2019). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. Archived from the original on 3 July 2023. Retrieved 24 May 2023.
- Green, Thomas Hill; Brink, David Owen (2003). Prolegomena to Ethics. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926643-2. Archived from the original on 2023-05-27. Retrieved 2023-05-27.
- Grendler, Paul (10 May 2010). "Humanism". Renaissance and Reformation. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780195399301-0002. ISBN 978-0-19-539930-1.
- Griffel, Frank (2020). "al-Ghazali". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 19 June 2023.
- Griffel, Frank (8 June 2021). The Formation of Post-Classical Philosophy in Islam. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-088634-9. Archived from the original on 9 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Gupta, Bina (19 April 2012). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy: Perspectives on Reality, Knowledge, and Freedom. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-65309-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Gutas, Dimitri (2016). "Ibn Sina [Avicenna]". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 April 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Haaparanta, Leila (2009). "1. Introduction". The development of modern logic. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513731-6.
- Hamilton, Paul (1 March 2004). Historicism. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-43781-8. Archived from the original on 23 June 2023. Retrieved 23 June 2023.
- Hammersley, Martyn (1 February 2018). Routledge Revivals: The Dilemma of Qualitative Method (1989): Herbert Blumer and the Chicago Tradition. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-03768-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 18 June 2023.
- Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2021). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 March 2019. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Heidegger, Martin (5 February 2015). The Beginning of Western Philosophy: Interpretation of Anaximander and Parmenides. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-01561-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Heller, Agnes (14 April 2016). A Theory of History. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-26883-3.
- Hindson, Ed; Caner, Ergun (1 May 2008). The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics: Surveying the Evidence for the Truth of Christianity. Harvest House Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7369-3635-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- Houlgate, Stephen (2005). An introduction to Hegel: Freedom, Truth, and History (2nd ed.). Blackwell.
- Hughes, Claretha; Gosney, Matthew W. (2016). The History of Human Resource Development: Understanding the Unexplored Philosophies, Theories, and Methodologies. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-52698-4. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-05-27.
- Hurka, Thomas (2021). "Moore's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 March 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Iannone, A. Pablo (15 April 2013). Dictionary of World Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-68043-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Illetterati, Luca; Miolli, Giovanna (16 December 2021). The Relevance of Hegel's Concept of Philosophy: From Classical German Philosophy to Contemporary Metaphilosophy. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-16260-0. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 26 June 2023.
- Imbo, Samuel Oluoch (1998). An introduction to African philosophy. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 0847688410.
- Inglis, John (9 October 2005). Medieval Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: In Islam, Judaism and Christianity. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-79088-2. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
- Iqbal, Muzaffar (2009). The Making of Islamic Science. The Other Press. ISBN 978-967-5062-31-5. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-08.
- Jackson, Roy (5 February 2014). What is Islamic Philosophy?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-81404-7. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
- Janaway, Christopher (9 March 1989). Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-152013-6. Archived from the original on 4 June 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Janz, Bruce B. (2009). Philosophy in an African Place. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-3668-3.
- Jha, Meenakshi (1 January 2022). Subaltern Saints in India: Women and Sudras in Bhakti Movement. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 978-81-208-4299-1.
- Juergensmeyer, Mark; Roof, Wade Clark (2012). Encyclopedia of Global Religion. SAGE. ISBN 978-0-7619-2729-7. Archived from the original on 2023-07-11. Retrieved 2023-06-10.
- Kasulis, Thomas (2022). "Japanese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Kasulis, Thomas P. (2016). "Japanese philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G100-1. ISBN 9780415250696.
- Kasulis, Thomas P. (2016a). "Logic in Japan". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. lead section, 2. Nishida’s logic of basho and logic of the predicate. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G108-1. ISBN 9780415250696.
- Kasulis, Thomas P. (2013). "Japanese philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 13 December 2018. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Kaye, Sharon M. (1 December 2012). Medieval Philosophy: A Beginner's Guide. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-78074-168-0. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Kaylor, Noel Harold; Phillips, Philip Edward (3 May 2012). A Companion to Boethius in the Middle Ages. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-18354-4. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Kenny, Anthony (2005). Medieval Philosophy. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875277-6.
- Kenny, Anthony (2007). Philosophy in the Modern World. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875279-0.
- Kenny, Anthony (2006). The rise of modern philosophy. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875277-6.
- Kerr, Gaven. "Aquinas: Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Kim, Sungmoon (14 November 2019). Theorizing Confucian Virtue Politics: The Political Philosophy of Mencius and Xunzi. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-57739-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Komar, Bernard V. (7 March 2003). Christian Love. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-58901-296-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Kulke, Hermann; Rothermund, Dietmar (1998). A History of India. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-15482-6.
- Kurki, Milja (3 April 2008). Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-47076-6. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
- Kurtz, Lester R. (2012). Gods in the Global Village: The World's Religions in Sociological Perspective. Pine Forge Press. ISBN 978-1-4129-9125-4. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-15.
- Laerke, Mogens; Smith, Justin E. H.; Schliesser, Eric (August 2013). Philosophy and Its History: Aims and Methods in the Study of Early Modern Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-985716-6.
- Lagerlund, Henrik, ed. (2020). Encyclopedia of medieval philosophy: philosophy between 500 and 1500 (Second ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-94-024-1663-3.
- Lamprecht, Sterling P. (17 August 1939). "Historiography of Philosophy". The Journal of Philosophy. 36 (17). doi:10.2307/2018864. JSTOR 2018864.
- Lawson, Russell M. (2004). Science in the Ancient World: An Encyclopedia. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-85109-534-6. Archived from the original on 2023-05-28. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
- Leahey, Thomas Hardy (2 October 2017). A History of Psychology: From Antiquity to Modernity. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-22849-3. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
- Legg, Catherine; Hookway, Christopher (16 August 2008). "Pragmatism". lead section. Archived from the original on 8 October 2020. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Lévinas, Emmanuel (1995). The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's Phenomenology. Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-8101-1281-0. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
- Littlejohn, Ronnie (2023). "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 12 June 2023.
- Liu, JeeLoo (19 June 2017). Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-61914-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Long, A. A. (20 August 1986). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-05808-8. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- López-Farjeat, Luis Xavier (10 August 2021). Classical Islamic Philosophy: A Thematic Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-38926-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Lovat, Terence; Dally, Kerry; Clement, Neville; Toomey, Ron (6 July 2011). Values Pedagogy and Student Achievement: Contemporary Research Evidence. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-1563-9. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- MacDonald, Scott; Kretzmann, Norman (1996). "Medieval philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on 2023-05-09. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
- Mackey, David A.; Elvey, Kathryn M. (14 February 2020). Society, Ethics, and the Law: A Reader. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-1-284-19964-2. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Maharaj, Ayon (28 May 2020). The Bloomsbury Research Handbook of Vedanta. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-06325-9. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Makaryk, Irene Rima (1 January 1993). Encyclopedia of Contemporary Literary Theory: Approaches, Scholars, Terms. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0-8020-6860-6.
- Maraldo, John C. (2019). "Nishida Kitarō". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 9 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Marenbon, John, ed. (2004). III. Medieval Philosophy. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02846-9.
- Marenbon, John (2023). "Medieval Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 26 March 2023. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
- Marenbon, John (14 June 2012). The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy. OUP USA. ISBN 978-0-19-537948-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
- Marias, Julian (2 October 2012). History of Philosophy. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-12193-2. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Marino, Stefano; Terzi, Pietro (9 November 2020). Kant's 'Critique of Aesthetic Judgment' in the 20th Century: A Companion to Its Main Interpretations. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-059649-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
- Marshev, Vadim I. (13 January 2021). History of Management Thought: Genesis and Development from Ancient Origins to the Present Day. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-62337-1. Archived from the original on 24 June 2023. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
- Masud, Muhammad Khalid (18 August 2009). Islam and Modernity: Key Issues and Debates. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-3794-2.
- McEwan, Cheryl (20 November 2008). Postcolonialism and Development. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-08082-3.
- Menon, Sangeetha. "Vedanta, Advaita". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Meynard, Thierry; Major, Philippe (20 February 2023). Dao Companion to Liang Shuming's Philosophy. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-18002-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 22 June 2023.
- Moaddel, Mansoor (16 May 2005). Islamic Modernism, Nationalism, and Fundamentalism: Episode and Discourse. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-53333-9. Archived from the original on 23 August 2023. Retrieved 23 August 2023.
- Montero, Barbara Gail (28 April 2016). Thought in Action: Expertise and the Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-108170-5. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
- Moris, Zailan (5 November 2013). Revelation, Intellectual Intuition and Reason in the Philosophy of Mulla Sadra: An Analysis of the al-hikmah al-'arshiyyah. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-85866-6. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Mou, Bo, ed. (2009). History of Chinese philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-00286-5.
- Murphy, Madonna M. (25 April 2015). "Plato's Philosophy of Education and the Common Core Debate". Association for the Development of Philosophy Teaching - Spring Conference. Archived from the original on 3 May 2023. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
- Murphy, Mark (2019). "The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 24 May 2023. Retrieved 29 May 2023.
- Nasr, Seyyed Hossein; Leaman, Oliver (7 March 2013). History of Islamic Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-78043-1. Archived from the original on 7 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (11 May 2006). Islamic Philosophy from Its Origin to the Present: Philosophy in the Land of Prophecy. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-6800-5. Archived from the original on 7 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Nord, Warren (10 November 2010). Does God Make a Difference?: Taking Religion Seriously in Our Schools and Universities. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-989022-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- Nyiro, Lajos (8 July 2019). Literature and its interpretation. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-134194-1. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
- O'Meara, Dominic J. (30 June 1981). Neoplatonism and Christian Thought. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-1-4384-1511-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
- O'Regan, Gerard (16 September 2016). Guide to Discrete Mathematics: An Accessible Introduction to the History, Theory, Logic and Applications. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-44561-8. Archived from the original on 4 June 2023. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
- Ongaro, Edoardo (31 July 2020). Philosophy and Public Administration: An Introduction. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 978-1-83910-034-5. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 22 June 2023.
- Paranjape, Makarand R. (22 January 2016). Cultural Politics in Modern India: Postcolonial prospects, colourful cosmopolitanism, global proximities. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-35215-0. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Park, Peter K. J. (11 March 2013). Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-1-4384-4643-1. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Parker-Ryan, Sally (2023). "Ordinary Language Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 5 June 2023.
- Parkinson, G. H. R., ed. (2005). IV. The Renaissance and Seventeenth-century Rationalism. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02914-5.
- Pasnau, Robert; Dyke, Christina van (19 June 2014). The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-95292-7. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
- Penner, Sydney. "Scholasticism and Aristotelianism: Fourteenth to Seventeenth Centuries". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Pérez-Jara, Javier; Camprubí, Lino (August 2022). Science and Apocalypse in Bertrand Russell: A Cultural Sociology. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-7936-1848-1. Archived from the original on 2023-06-06. Retrieved 2023-06-06.
- Perrett, Roy W. (4 February 2016). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Poceski, Mario (14 February 2014). The Wiley Blackwell Companion to East and Inner Asian Buddhism. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-61035-0.
- Pooley, Jefferson D.; Rothenbuhler, Eric W. (31 October 2016). The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy, 4 Volume Set. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-29073-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Prince, Brainerd (20 January 2017). The Integral Philosophy of Aurobindo: Hermeneutics and the Study of Religion. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-19447-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Qi, Xiaoying (21 January 2014). Globalized Knowledge Flows and Chinese Social Theory. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-69162-3. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Raghuramaraju, A. (16 March 2016). Ramchandra Gandhi: The Man and His Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-91758-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Rambachan, Anantanand (1 February 2012). The Advaita Worldview: God, World, and Humanity. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-8131-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Rambachan, Anantanand (1 January 1994). The Limits of Scripture: Vivekananda's Reinterpretation of the Vedas. University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-1542-4. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Ramgotra, Manjeet; Choat, Simon (30 March 2023). Rethinking Political Thinkers. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884739-7. Archived from the original on 4 June 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Ranganathan, Shyam. "Ramanuja". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 7 September 2023.
- Raymond, Geuss (1996). "Critical theory". In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 9780415073103.
- Rée, Jonathan; Urmson, J. O. (30 September 2004). The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-33177-2. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Reisman, David C., ed. (1 January 2003). Before and After Avicenna: Proceedings of the First Conference of the Avicenna Study Group. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-12978-8. Archived from the original on 24 June 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
- Rescher, Nicholas (23 October 2014). Metaphilosophy: Philosophy in Philosophical Perspective. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-0-7391-9978-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
- Rizvi, Sajjad (2021). "Mulla Sadra". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 May 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
- Robb, Nesca A. (13 April 2021). Neoplatonism of the Italian Renaissance. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-36288-6. Archived from the original on 31 May 2023. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
- Ruether, Rosemary Radford (26 November 2004). Integrating Ecofeminism, Globalization, and World Religions. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4616-3822-3. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- Russell, Jeffrey Burton (22 February 2005). Medieval Civilization. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-59752-103-1. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
- Ruzsa, Ferenc (2023). "Sankhya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 May 2019. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Safi, Omid (2005). "Modernism: Islamic Modernism". Encyclopedia of Religion. Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 978-0-02-865733-2.
- Santinello, Giovanni; Piaia, Gregorio (1 December 2010). Models of the History of Philosophy: Volume II: From Cartesian Age to Brucker. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-90-481-9507-7. Archived from the original on 3 July 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Santis, Daniele De; Hopkins, Burt C.; Majolino, Claudio (24 August 2020). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-17058-0. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Scharfstein, Ben-Ami (1 January 1998). A Comparative History of World Philosophy: From the Upanishads to Kant. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-3683-7. Archived from the original on 3 July 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
- Seshadri, Kandadai (1996). "Ramanuja: Social Influence of His Life and Teaching". Economic and Political Weekly. 31 (5). ISSN 0012-9976. JSTOR 4403749.
- Shanker, Stuart G., ed. (2004). IX. Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02947-3.
- Singer, Peter (2 May 2023). "Ethics". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2 May 2008. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Sisko, John E. (6 July 2018). Philosophy of Mind in Antiquity: The History of the Philosophy of Mind, Volume 1. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-01965-4. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Slingerland, Edward (24 May 2007). Effortless Action: Wu-wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-987457-6. Archived from the original on 3 July 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Smart, Ninian (2008). World philosophies (Rev. 2nd ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-41188-2.
- Spade, Paul Vincent; Panaccio, Claude (2019). "William of Ockham". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 7 October 2019. Retrieved 29 May 2023.
- Stehn, Alexander V. (2023). "Latin American Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
- Stevenson, Jay (1 April 2014). Philosophy (4th ed.). Penguin. ISBN 978-1-61564-538-1. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 1 June 2023.
- Sweeney, E. (30 April 2016). Logic, Theology and Poetry in Boethius, Anselm, Abelard, and Alan of Lille: Words in the Absence of Things. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-06373-1. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Sydnor, Jon Paul (29 March 2012). Ramanuja and Schleiermacher: Toward a Constructive Comparative Theology. James Clarke & Company Limited. ISBN 978-0-227-90035-2.
- Taylor, Christopher Charles Whiston, ed. (1997). I. From the beginning to Plato. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-06272-5.
- Tebbit, Mark (4 July 2013). The Philosophy of Law: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-58277-7. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
- Ten, C. L., ed. (2005). VII. The Nineteenth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-03066-0.
- Thompson, John M. (2008). Understanding Prajñā: Sengzhao's "Wild Words" and the Search for Wisdom. Peter Lang. ISBN 978-0-8204-8826-4. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
- Tritten, Tyler; Whistler, Daniel (7 December 2018). Nature, Speculation and the Return to Schelling. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-37941-0. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Tucker, Spencer C. (21 September 2017). Enduring Controversies in Military History: Critical Analyses and Context [2 volumes]. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-4408-4120-0.
- Vallgarda, Signild; Koch, Lene, eds. (2008). Research Methods in Public Health. Munksgaard Danmark. ISBN 978-87-628-0794-5. Archived from the original on 2023-06-22. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
- Vanamali (30 January 2015). The Science of the Rishis: The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-62055-387-9. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Verene, Donald Phillip (20 June 2008). The History of Philosophy: A Reader's Guide. Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-8101-5197-0. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
- Vesey, Godfrey, ed. (18 June 1976). Impressions of Empiricism. Springer. ISBN 978-1-349-02804-7. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
- Vogt, Katja (2022). "Ancient Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 17 March 2023. Retrieved 26 May 2023.
- Waithe, Mary Ellen (1995). A history of women philosophers. 4: Contemporary women philosophers 1900 - today. Dordrecht: Nijhoff. ISBN 9780792328087.
- Wang, Yueqing; Bao, Qinggang; Guan, Guoxing (16 March 2020). History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-15-2572-8. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Warren, Karen J. (16 December 2008). An Unconventional History of Western Philosophy: Conversations Between Men and Women Philosophers. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7425-6460-2. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
- Wheeler, Michael (2020). "Martin Heidegger". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2.2.1 The Question. Archived from the original on 6 February 2022. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
- Whistler, Daniel (28 March 2013). Schelling's Theory of Symbolic Language: Forming the System of Identity. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-967373-5. Archived from the original on 3 June 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
- Wiredu, Kwasi (15 April 2008). A Companion to African Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-99737-6.
- Wolfson, Elliot R. (3 February 2014). Giving Beyond the Gift: Apophasis and Overcoming Theomania. Fordham Univ Press. ISBN 978-0-8232-5572-6. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
- Yu, Yih-Hsien (2023). "Chinese Philosophy, Modern". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 14 June 2023. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Zhang, Xuezhi (26 April 2021). History of Chinese Philosophy in the Ming Dynasty. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-15-8963-8. Archived from the original on 25 June 2023. Retrieved 25 June 2023.